- tags
- Phenomenology
Notes
Acknowledgements
General introduction
I was appalled by the extent to which science had reneged both on its sense of democratic responsibility and on its original commitment to enlarge the scope of human knowledge, and had allowed itself to become subservient to the demands of the military-industrial complex.
NOTER_PAGE: (16 0.36459114778694673 . 0.7139830508474576)
as a professional scientist one could never be more than a small cog in a huge juggernaut of an enterprise.
NOTER_PAGE: (16 0.4553638409602401 . 0.486228813559322)
a single, underlying fault upon which the entire edifice of Western thought and science has been built – namely that which separates the ‘two worlds’ of humanity and nature.
NOTER_PAGE: (16 0.7831957989497375 . 0.3972457627118644)
essential complementarity of the biogenetic and sociocultural dimensions of human existence.
NOTER_PAGE: (17 0.33308327081770445 . 0.3114406779661017)
Perception, Gibson argued, is not the achievement of a mind in a body, but of the organism as a whole in its environment, and is tantamount to the organism’s own exploratory movement through the world. If mind is anywhere, then, it is not ‘inside the head’ rather than ‘out there’ in the world.
NOTER_PAGE: (18 0.15678919729932483 . 0.10699152542372882)
calls for a kind of ‘relational thinking’ that goes right against the grain of the ‘population thinking’ that has been de rigueur
NOTER_PAGE: (18 0.8837209302325582 . 0.5317796610169492)
The characteristics of organisms, they argue, are not so much expressed as generated in the course of development, arising as emergent properties of the fields of relationship set up through their presence and activity within a particular environment.
NOTER_PAGE: (19 0.4711177794448612 . 0.388771186440678)
much if not all of what we are accustomed to call cultural variation in fact consists of variations of skills.
NOTER_PAGE: (20 0.10952738184546137 . 0.2574152542372881)
reason why we cannot escape ‘the West’, or avoid the anxieties of modernity. It is that our very activity, in thinking and writing, is underpinned by a belief in the absolute worth of disciplined, rational inquiry. In this book, it is to this belief that the terms ‘Western’ and ‘modern’ refer. And however much we may object to the dichotomies to which it gives rise, between humanity and nature, intelligence and instinct, the mental and the material, and so on, the art of critical disputation on these matters is precisely what ‘the West’ is all about.
NOTER_PAGE: (21 0.8005284015852048 . 0.13246268656716417)
PART I: Livelihood
questions of how people interact, practically and technically, with the resources of their environment in obtaining a livelihood tend to be treated separately from questions of how their lifeworld is imaginatively ‘constructed’, in myth, religion and ceremony.
NOTER_PAGE: (24 0.404887714663144 . 0.15764925373134328)
For the Ojibwa, knowledge is grounded in experience, understood as a coupling of the movement of one’s awareness to the movement of aspects of the world.
NOTER_PAGE: (26 0.4346103038309115 . 0.6231343283582089)
what the Ojibwa have arrived at is not an alternative science of nature but a poetics of dwelling.
NOTER_PAGE: (26 0.5726552179656539 . 0.3498134328358209)
production of what we in the West would call ‘art’ should be understood not as ways of representing the world of experience on a higher, more symbolic plane, but of probing more deeply into it and discovering the significance that lies there.
NOTER_PAGE: (26 0.7153236459709379 . 0.1707089552238806)
Culture, nature, environment: steps to an ecology of life
the Cree draw a parallel between the pursuit of animals and the seduction of young women, and liken killing to sexual intercourse. In this light, killing appears not as a termination of life but as an act that is critical to its regeneration.
NOTER_PAGE: (28 0.6965879265091863 . 0.3358042994810971)
NOTER_PAGE: (29 0.4881889763779528 . 0.13787991104521868)
What the anthropologist calls a cosmology is, for the 6 people themselves, a lifeworld.
NOTER_PAGE: (29 0.8677165354330708 . 0.352112676056338)
double disengagement of the observer from the world. The first sets up a division between humanity and nature; the second establishes a division, within humanity, between ‘native’ or ‘indigenous’ people, who live in cultures, and enlightened Westerners, who do not.
NOTER_PAGE: (30 0.22992125984251968 . 0.8072646404744255)
a kind of knowledge that is fundamentally resistant to 20 transmission in an authorised textual form, independently of the contexts of its instanti- 1 ation in the world.
NOTER_PAGE: (31 0.4167979002624672 . 0.2965159377316531)
NOTER_PAGE: (31 0.5039370078740157 . 0.2016308376575241)
NOTER_PAGE: (31 0.5380577427821522 . 0.3506300963676797)
NOTER_PAGE: (31 0.6918635170603674 . 0.25129725722757595)
NOTER_PAGE: (32 0.5931758530183727 . 0.2157153446997776)
Lévi-Strauss anchors the mind very firmly in the workings of the human brain.
NOTER_PAGE: (32 0.6094488188976378 . 0.6753150481838398)
structured through and through,
NOTER_PAGE: (32 0.7669291338582677 . 0.363232023721275)
The point about movement is critical. For Lévi-Strauss, both the mind and 30 the world remain fixed and immutable, while information passes across the interface 1 between them. In Bateson’s account, by contrast, information only exists thanks to the 2 movement of the perceiver relative to his or her surroundings.
NOTER_PAGE: (33 0.589501312335958 . 0.23202372127501852)
we draw distinctions, in the sense not of representing them graphi- 7 cally, but of ‘pulling them out’.
NOTER_PAGE: (33 0.7144356955380577 . 0.31208302446256486)
NOTER_PAGE: (34 0.1779527559055118 . 0.29429206819866566)
life- history could be nothing more than the realisation or ‘writing out’ of a programme
NOTER_PAGE: (34 0.29658792650918636 . 0.8131949592290585)
NOTER_PAGE: (34 0.4047244094488189 . 0.19644180874722014)
‘organism plus environment’ should denote not a compound of two things, but one indivisible totality. That totality is, in effect, a developmental system (cf. Oyama 1985), and an ecology of life – in my terms – is one that would deal with the dynamics of such systems.
NOTER_PAGE: (34 0.6740157480314961 . 0.7405485544848035)
what we may call mind is the cutting edge of the life process itself, the ever-moving front of what Alfred North Whitehead (1929: 314) called a ‘creative advance into novelty’.
NOTER_PAGE: (34 0.8325459317585302 . 0.2742772424017791)
But information, in itself, is not knowledge, nor do we become any more knowledgeable through its accumulation. Our knowledgeability consists, rather, in the capacity to situate such information, and understand its meaning, within the context of a direct perceptual engagement with our environments. And we develop this capacity, I contend, by having things shown to us.
NOTER_PAGE: (36 0.7790026246719159 . 0.32765011119347665)
What each generation 2 contributes to the next, in this process, is an education of attention
NOTER_PAGE: (37 0.10131233595800525 . 0.7071905114899926)
Langer contends that the meaning of art should be found 2 in the art object itself, as it is presented to our awareness, rather than in what it might be 3 supposed to represent or signify.
NOTER_PAGE: (37 0.7989501312335958 . 0.3795404002965159)
NOTER_PAGE: (38 0.29763779527559053 . 0.5663454410674573)
Janáček is not just hearing, he is listening. That 2 is to say, his perception is grounded in an act of attention. Like watching and feeling, 3 listening is something people do
NOTER_PAGE: (39 0.10761154855643044 . 0.3936249073387694)
sound, 9 as Janáček wrote, ‘grows out of our entire being . . . There is no sound that is broken away 20 1 from the tree of life ’
NOTER_PAGE: (39 0.4036745406824147 . 0.29577464788732394)
in telling in this other sense, he is no more 3 aiming to produce a record or transcription of what happened than was Janáček, when 4 he wrote down the sounds of the waves.
NOTER_PAGE: (39 0.8162729658792651 . 0.47516679021497404)
an intelligence that was completely detached from the conditions of life in the world could not think the thoughts it does.
NOTER_PAGE: (40 0.5753280839895013 . 0.16604892512972572)
NOTER_PAGE: (40 0.6787401574803149 . 0.3061527057079318)
The optimal forager and economic man
NOTER_PAGE: (42 0.6074035453597497 . 0.10751104565537555)
NOTER_PAGE: (42 0.7653806047966633 . 0.5787923416789396)
What, then, of non-human animals? They, too, seem to come out with strategies of 8 resource procurement which would look eminently rational, had they worked these strategies 9 out for themselves. But of course, you say, they have not. The animals have had their 20 strategies worked out for them in advance, by the evolutionary force of natural selection.
NOTER_PAGE: (43 0.384251968503937 . 0.15789473684210525)
Is the human hunter-gatherer, then, a version of economic man or a species of optimal forager?
NOTER_PAGE: (44 0.08915537017726799 . 0.12886597938144329)
The rationality of the optimal forager, by contrast, is installed at the very heart of nature, while the specifically human domain of society and culture is seen as a source of external normative bias
NOTER_PAGE: (44 0.20855057351407716 . 0.5419734904270986)
contradiction between the notions, on the one hand, that the forager’s ‘strategy of adjustment’ is the result of a series of choices about where to go and what to procure, and on the other hand, that as an ‘adap- tive pattern’ it is the product of an evolutionary process.
NOTER_PAGE: (44 0.607924921793535 . 0.5662739322533137)
the Cree hunter is unlikely ever to encounter the same conditions from one year to the next
NOTER_PAGE: (44 0.815954118873827 . 0.1053019145802651)
It is not so clear, however, that the pattern has ‘evolved’ in the Darwinian sense, or that its emergence has anything to do with the process of natural selection.
NOTER_PAGE: (45 0.34932221063607927 . 0.2503681885125184)
I know of no recent author who has seriously suggested that the behavioural 9 variability apparent from ethnographic studies of human hunter-gatherers might be attrib- 40 uted to inter-populational genetic differences. Instead it is proposed that the instructions 1 underwriting human foraging behaviour are cultural
NOTER_PAGE: (45 0.7471324296141815 . 0.2304860088365243)
merely applying a set of deci- sion rules acquired more or less unselfconsciously from his seniors, and whose prevalence in the society is due not to their perceived efficacy but to the fact that they served his predecessors well,
NOTER_PAGE: (46 0.1251303441084463 . 0.22459499263622976)
genuine choices may still have to be made. But they are made within a received strategic framework, they are not about what framework to adopt.
NOTER_PAGE: (46 0.29979144942648595 . 0.24594992636229748)
Observing that human behaviour often seems far from optimal, the blame for the discrepancy is placed squarely upon culture itself !
NOTER_PAGE: (46 0.4181438998957247 . 0.2614138438880707)
cultural heritage, far from underwriting his ability to come up with an effective strategy, is actually liable to prevent him from recognising the best course of action
NOTER_PAGE: (46 0.870177267987487 . 0.11266568483063329)
optimal foraging theorists are trying to have it both ways,
NOTER_PAGE: (47 0.2643378519290928 . 0.20029455081001474)
NOTER_PAGE: (47 0.5563086548488009 . 0.22754050073637702)
He could not have chosen to do other than what he actually does, any more than the muskrat could have chosen not to enter the trap, or the warbler not to migrate. For as a product of ‘encul- turation’, the hunter is as stuck with his heritage as are the muskrat and the bird with their respective sets of genes.
NOTER_PAGE: (48 0.08706986444212722 . 0.3284241531664212)
that a prerequisite for any theory of calcu- lative adaptation is an account of human nature which must necessarily be couched in populational terms.
NOTER_PAGE: (48 0.35036496350364965 . 0.23269513991163476)
if we want to explain where these beliefs and preferences came from in the first place – if, that is, we seek the source of human intentions – then we have to show how they may have emerged through a history of natural selection.
NOTER_PAGE: (48 0.5568627450980391 . 0.10522151898734176)
evolutionary ecology seeks to 4 show how behaviour is sensitively responsive to variations in the environment, but lacks 5 a coherent account of human nature; evolutionary psychology seeks to construct just such 6 an account, but in doing so is insensitive to the fine-tuning of human behaviour to environ- 7 mental conditions.
NOTER_PAGE: (49 0.31484593837535013 . 0.2444620253164557)
problem lies at the heart of the Darwinian paradigm itself.
NOTER_PAGE: (49 0.5076467686235817 . 0.38118466898954706)
Given that social learning occupies such a central place in their theory – as central, 5 indeed, as genetic replication – it is rather surprising that evolutionary ecologists have 6 devoted almost no attention to how it occurs.
NOTER_PAGE: (51 0.50419338924519 . 0.15958188153310104)
a whole inventory of rules 30 and representations is miraculously downloaded into the passively receptive mind of the 1 novice.
NOTER_PAGE: (51 0.5934879131721756 . 0.13310104529616726)
NOTER_PAGE: (52 0.2989639861864825 . 0.3686411149825784)
not possible, in practice, to separate the sphere of the novice’s involvement with other persons from that of his involvement with the non-human environment.
NOTER_PAGE: (52 0.3344844597927973 . 0.38606271777003487)
to observe is actively to attend to the movements of others; to imitate is to align that attention to the movement of one’s own practical orientation towards the environment.
NOTER_PAGE: (52 0.5559940799210656 . 0.09965156794425087)
what is involved, as I showed in the last chapter, is not a transmission of representations, as the enculturation model implies, but an education of attention.
NOTER_PAGE: (52 0.6260483473112975 . 0.3519163763066202)
it makes no sense to speak of ‘culture’ as an independent body of context-free knowledge,
NOTER_PAGE: (52 0.694622594967933 . 0.5135888501742161)
The accomplished hunter consults the world, not representations inside his head. The implications of this conclusion cannot be overemphasised, since they strike at the very core of neo-Darwinian theory itself.
NOTER_PAGE: (52 0.9003453379378392 . 0.47038327526132406)
NOTER_PAGE: (53 0.21164282190429207 . 0.7275261324041812)
They appear to stand, thus, on opposite sides of an overriding division between reason and nature, freedom and necessity, subjectivity and objectivity.
NOTER_PAGE: (53 0.5362604834731131 . 0.28710801393728225)
Hunting and gathering as ways of perceiving the environment
systematically reject the ontological dualism of that tradition of thought and science which – as a kind of shorthand – we call ‘Western’, and of which the dichotomy between nature and culture is the prototypical instance.
NOTER_PAGE: (55 0.4188455846077948 . 0.2445993031358885)
the world can only be ‘nature’ for a being that does not inhabit it, yet only through inhabiting can the world be constituted, in relation to a being, as its environment.
NOTER_PAGE: (55 0.5734477536597677 . 0.5481111903064861)
distinguish between two kinds or versions of nature: ‘really natural’ nature (the object of study for natural scientists) and ‘culturally perceived’ nature (the object of study for social and cultural anthropologists).
NOTER_PAGE: (56 0.2979261507334345 . 0.1792857142857143)
NOTER_PAGE: (56 0.47091552857865454 . 0.7107142857142857)
take as ‘given’ the very concepts that, in the first part of the statement, are said to be historically relative.
NOTER_PAGE: (56 0.8856853818917552 . 0.7021428571428572)
infinite regress: if the opposed categories of 6 ‘nature’ and ‘culture’ are themselves cultural constructs, then so must be the culture that 7 constructs them,
NOTER_PAGE: (57 0.1770359129994942 . 0.245)
hunter-gatherers do not, as a rule, approach their 1 environment as an external world of nature that has to be ‘grasped’ conceptually and 2 appropriated symbolically within the terms of an imposed cultural design,
NOTER_PAGE: (57 0.26150733434496715 . 0.4635714285714286)
follow the lead of 4 hunter-gatherers in taking the human condition to be that of a being immersed from the 5 start, like other creatures, in an active, practical and perceptual engagement with 6 constituents of the dwelt-in world.
NOTER_PAGE: (57 0.4865958523014669 . 0.42214285714285715)
The contrast, I repeat, is not between alternative views of the world; it is rather between two ways of apprehending
NOTER_PAGE: (57 0.6742539200809308 . 0.6385714285714286)
NOTER_PAGE: (58 0.727364693980779 . 0.5957142857142858)
cultivators, by contrast, the environment is likened to an ancestor rather than a parent, which yields its bounty only reciprocally, in return for favours rendered.
NOTER_PAGE: (58 0.8017197774405666 . 0.24571428571428572)
NOTER_PAGE: (59 0.10925644916540213 . 0.5621428571428572)
NOTER_PAGE: (59 0.21345472938796156 . 0.4307142857142857)
assumed separation between two domains: the domain of human persons and social relations, wherein parenting and sharing are matters of everyday, commonsense reality; and the domain of the non-human environment, the forest with its plants and animals, relations with which are understood by drawing, for analogy, on those intrinsic to the first domain.
NOTER_PAGE: (59 0.3844208396560445 . 0.42)
Parenting is not a construction that is projected onto acts of this kind, it rather subsists in them,
NOTER_PAGE: (60 0.19119878603945373 . 0.11071428571428571)
NOTER_PAGE: (60 0.43753161355589276 . 0.21)
In their account (lower diagram) there are not two worlds, of nature and society, but just one, saturated with personal powers, and embracing both humans, the animals and plants on which they depend, and the features of the land- scape in which they live and move.
NOTER_PAGE: (62 0.2453211937278705 . 0.39571428571428574)
hunters and gatherers consider time devoted to forays in the forest to be well spent, even if it yields little or nothing by way of useful return: there is, as Bird-David puts it, ‘a concern with the activity itself ’
NOTER_PAGE: (62 0.4704097116843703 . 0.565)
only catch an animal when the animal is given to them.
NOTER_PAGE: (63 0.13707637835103692 . 0.135)
‘respectful activity towards the animals enhances the readiness with which they give themselves,
NOTER_PAGE: (63 0.20536165907941326 . 0.81)
partners with humans in an encompassing ‘cosmic economy of sharing’.
NOTER_PAGE: (63 0.5194739504299444 . 0.6285714285714286)
Underwriting the Western view of the uniqueness of the human species is the fundamental axiom that personhood as a state of being is not open to non-human animal kinds.
NOTER_PAGE: (63 0.6059686393525544 . 0.51)
always appropriate to ask ‘who did it?’ and ‘why?’ rather than ‘how does that work?’
NOTER_PAGE: (64 0.09256449165402125 . 0.65)
‘human persons are not set over and against a material context of inert nature, but rather are one species of person in a network of reciprocating persons’
NOTER_PAGE: (64 0.296914516944866 . 0.3028571428571429)
‘reinter- preted’ as anthropomorphic beings
NOTER_PAGE: (64 0.4865958523014669 . 0.375)
This does not mean, of course, that they fail to differentiate between humans and animals. To the contrary, they are acutely concerned about such differences.
NOTER_PAGE: (64 0.8340920586747598 . 0.11071428571428571)
implication that in modern biology appears in the guise of the doctrine of genetic preformation. With this view, personal powers – of awareness, agency and intentionality – can form no part of the organism as such, but must necessarily be ‘added on’ as capacities not of body but of mind,
NOTER_PAGE: (65 0.8502781992918563 . 0.49785714285714283)
‘the term pimaatisiiwin, “life”, was translated by one Cree man as “continuous birth”’
NOTER_PAGE: (66 0.1734951947395043 . 0.6264285714285714)
NOTER_PAGE: (66 0.22711178553363684 . 0.26071428571428573)
consciousness is not supplementary to organic life but is, so to speak, its advancing front
NOTER_PAGE: (66 0.33181588265048056 . 0.19785714285714287)
A creature can have a point of view because its action in the world is, at the same time, a process of attending to it.
NOTER_PAGE: (66 0.7288821446636318 . 0.13)
In short, animals do not participate with humans qua persons only in a domain of virtual reality, as represented within culturally constructed, intentional worlds, superim- posed upon the naturally given substratum of organism–environment interactions. They participate as real-world creatures, endowed with powers of feeling and autonomous action, whose characteristic behaviours, temperaments and sensibilities one gets to know in the very course of one’s everyday practical dealings with them. In this regard, dealing with non-human animals is not fundamentally different from dealing with fellow humans.
NOTER_PAGE: (67 0.1588265048052605 . 0.15642857142857142)
If persons inscribe their identities into the landscape as historically constituted, it is from the transhistorical level of the Dreaming that these identities are initially derived. Thus each person takes his or her primary identity from a particular named place, and is regarded as the incarnation of the ancestor whose activity made that place. That is why, as Myers notes (1986: 50), ‘it is not unusual . . . to hear people describe actions of the Dreaming in the first person’. For in speaking about my ancestor, I am speaking about myself.
NOTER_PAGE: (68 0.5715730905412241 . 0.12714285714285714)
When social relations are spoken of, as they often are, in terms of relations between places, the comparison does not draw a parallel across separate domains of society and the physical world, but rather reveals that – at a more fundamental ontological level – these relations are equivalent. That level is the Dreaming.
NOTER_PAGE: (68 0.7455741021750126 . 0.22142857142857142)
‘the Koyukon must move with the forces of their surroundings, not attempting to control, master or fundamentally alter them’
NOTER_PAGE: (69 0.4683864441072332 . 0.5978571428571429)
we find a complete inversion, such that meanings that the 3 people claim to discover in the landscape are attributed to the minds of the people them- 4 selves, and are said to be mapped onto the landscape. And the latter, drained of all 5 significance as a prelude to its cultural construction, is reduced to space, a vacuum to the 6 plenum of culture.
NOTER_PAGE: (69 0.8179059180576631 . 0.26071428571428573)
New knowledge comes from creative acts of discovery rather than imagining, from attending more closely to the environment rather than reassembling one’s picture of it along new conceptual lines.
NOTER_PAGE: (71 0.10723318158826506 . 0.5778571428571428)
Do not these stories, along with the accompanying songs, designs, sacred objects and the like, amount to a kind of modelling of reality, a representation of the world that native people might consult as Westerners would consult a map? I think not. People, once familiar with a country, have no need of maps, and get their bearings from attending to the landscape itself rather than from some inner representation of the same. Importantly, Myers notes that among the Pintupi the meanings of songs remain obscure to those who do not already know the country,
NOTER_PAGE: (71 0.20890237733940314 . 0.22285714285714286)
NOTER_PAGE: (71 0.6595852301466869 . 0.5264285714285715)
the lands of the Koyukon, according to Nelson, ‘are no more a wilderness than are farmlands to a farmer or streets to a city dweller’
NOTER_PAGE: (72 0.28072837632776937 . 0.4614285714285714)
NOTER_PAGE: (72 0.541224076884168 . 0.21857142857142858)
NOTER_PAGE: (72 0.6054628224582701 . 0.4564285714285714)
the Dreaming is transhistorical, not prehistorical.
NOTER_PAGE: (72 0.7784522003034902 . 0.14285714285714285)
From trust to domination: an alternative history of human-animal relations
the domain in which human persons are involved as social beings with one another cannot be rigidly set apart from the domain of their involvement with non-human components of the environment. Hence, any qualitative transformation in environmental relations is likely to be manifested similarly both in the relationships that humans extend towards animals and in those that obtain among themselves in society.
NOTER_PAGE: (76 0.7647951441578149 . 0.37785714285714284)
the proper destiny of human beings is to overcome the condition of animality
NOTER_PAGE: (77 0.18715225088517956 . 0.24071428571428571)
hunters and gatherers exploit ‘wild’ or non-domesticated resources, whereas farmers and herdsmen exploit domesticated ones
NOTER_PAGE: (77 0.6246838644410724 . 0.3271428571428571)
depicted as though engaged, like other animal predators, in the continual pursuit of fugitive prey, locked in a struggle for existence which – on account of the poverty of their technology – is not yet won.
NOTER_PAGE: (77 0.7814871016691958 . 0.3335714285714286)
fundamental metaphysical dualism – one that seems peculiar to the discourse which, as a convenient shorthand, we can call ‘Western’, to the extent of being its defining feature. This is the separation of two, mutually exclusive domains of being to which we attach the labels ‘humanity’ and ‘nature’.
NOTER_PAGE: (78 0.1608497723823976 . 0.10642857142857143)
when we speak of domestication as an intervention in nature, as we are inclined to do, humanity’s transcendence over the natural world is already presupposed.
NOTER_PAGE: (78 0.469903894790086 . 0.24071428571428571)
In order to produce, humans have to achieve such command or mastery over nature as to be able to impress their own, calculated designs upon the face of the earth. Thus ‘the further removed men are from animals, . . . the more their effect on nature assumes the character of premeditated, planned action directed towards definite preconceived ends’
NOTER_PAGE: (78 0.52250885179565 . 0.5271428571428571)
reminds of Bateson on “purposive consciousness” as original sin (Steps to An Ecology of Mind)
Human beings, as social persons, can own; animals, as natural objects, are only ownable. Thus the concept of appropriation, just as the concept of intervention, sets humanity, the world of persons, on a pedestal above the natural world of things.
NOTER_PAGE: (79 0.46880650994575046 . 0.5127713920817369)
Unlike the individual in modern Western society who always wants more than he can get, however well-off he may be, the wants of the hunter-gatherer, Sahlins argued, are very limited. What one has, one shares, and there is no point in accumulating material property that would only be an impediment, given the demands of nomadic life.
NOTER_PAGE: (80 0.8503616636528029 . 0.13409961685823757)
There is no concept of scarcity.
NOTER_PAGE: (81 0.08725135623869801 . 0.210727969348659)
an apparent lack of foresight, or of concern for the future.
NOTER_PAGE: (81 0.1252260397830018 . 0.4137931034482759)
The important thing, for them, is that food should ‘go round’ rather than that it should ‘last out’.
NOTER_PAGE: (81 0.1767631103074141 . 0.13537675606641125)
hunter-gatherers treat the environment itself as their storehouse, rather than setting aside supplies
NOTER_PAGE: (81 0.3114828209764918 . 0.67816091954023)
NOTER_PAGE: (81 0.4344484629294756 . 0.3103448275862069)
what it suggests about peoples’ commitments both to the non-human environment and to one another.
NOTER_PAGE: (81 0.626130198915009 . 0.516602809706258)
‘people are not dependent on specific other people,
NOTER_PAGE: (81 0.7839059674502712 . 0.43039591315453385)
people have to look after or care for the country
NOTER_PAGE: (82 0.1256781193490054 . 0.4655172413793104)
animals will not return to hunters who have treated them badly
NOTER_PAGE: (82 0.3331826401446655 . 0.314176245210728)
This emphasis on the careful and prudent use of resources, and on the avoidance of waste, seems a far cry from the image, presented by Sahlins, of original affluence,
NOTER_PAGE: (82 0.484629294755877 . 0.13218390804597702)
success in present hunting depends on personal relationships built up and maintained with animal powers through a history of previous hunts,
NOTER_PAGE: (82 0.523508137432188 . 0.384418901660281)
the meat that the hunter obtains now is a return on the investment of attention
NOTER_PAGE: (82 0.575497287522604 . 0.32950191570881227)
there is no way in which native people can be accommodated within schemes of scientific conservation except as parts of the wildlife, that is as constituents of the nature that is to be conserved. They cannot themselves be conservers, because the principles and practice of scientific conservation enjoin a degree of detachment which is incompatible with the kind of involvement with the environment that is essential to hunting and gathering as a way of life.
NOTER_PAGE: (83 0.34945750452079566 . 0.5587484035759899)
caring for an environment is like caring for people: it requires a deep, personal and affectionate involvement,
NOTER_PAGE: (84 0.09041591320072333 . 0.6832694763729247)
a hunt that is successfully consummated with a kill is taken as proof of amicable relations
NOTER_PAGE: (84 0.41726943942133815 . 0.1724137931034483)
the encounter, at the moment of the kill, is – to them – essentially non-violent.
NOTER_PAGE: (84 0.4715189873417721 . 0.5306513409961686)
This principle which, I maintain, inheres equally in the activities of sharing and in those of hunting and gathering, is that of trust.
NOTER_PAGE: (84 0.8322784810126582 . 0.18007662835249044)
The essence of trust is a peculiar combination of autonomy and dependency.
NOTER_PAGE: (84 0.876130198915009 . 0.12835249042145594)
Although you depend on a favourable response, that response comes entirely on the initiative and volition of the other party. Any attempt to impose a response, to lay down conditions or obligations that the other is bound to follow, would represent a betrayal of trust and a negation of the relationship.
NOTER_PAGE: (85 0.10669077757685352 . 0.3773946360153257)
hunter-gatherers assume the providence of nature and do not consider the possibility of starvation.
NOTER_PAGE: (86 0.2283001808318264 . 0.37931034482758624)
The animals in the environment of the hunter do not simply go their own way, but are supposed to act with the hunter in mind. They are not just ‘there’ for the hunter to find and take as he will; rather they present themselves to him.
NOTER_PAGE: (86 0.4534358047016275 . 0.13282247765006386)
why hunters aim to take only what is revealed to them and do not press for more. To describe this orientation as ‘opportunism’ is misleading, for it is not a matter of taking what you can get but of accepting what is given.
NOTER_PAGE: (86 0.64376130198915 . 0.3167305236270754)
Woodburn’s error, as we can now see, was to assume that dependency on specific other people entails loss of autonomy. This is not necessarily so, for it is precisely in relations of trust that autonomy is retained despite dependency.
NOTER_PAGE: (86 0.8874321880650994 . 0.7120051085568327)
That is why hunters attach such enormous importance to knowledge and its acquisition. This is not knowledge in the natural scientific sense, of things and how they work. It is rather as we would speak of it in relation to persons: to ‘know’ someone is to be in a position to approach him directly with a fair expectation of the likely response, to be familiar with that person’s past history and sensible to his tastes, moods and idiosyncrasies. You get to know other human persons by sharing with them, that is by experiencing their companionship.
NOTER_PAGE: (87 0.2970162748643761 . 0.13537675606641125)
Herdsmen do indeed care for their animals, but it is care of a quite different kind from that extended by hunters. For one thing, the animals are presumed to lack the capacity to reciprocate.
NOTER_PAGE: (87 0.6754068716094033 . 0.46296296296296297)
They are cared for, but they are not themselves empowered to care.
NOTER_PAGE: (87 0.8318264014466545 . 0.13665389527458494)
the relationship of pastoral care, quite unlike that of the hunter towards animals, is founded on a principle not of trust but of domination.
NOTER_PAGE: (87 0.8688969258589512 . 0.2298850574712644)
the use of force is predicated on the assumption that the slave is a being with the capacity to act and suffer, and in that sense a person.
NOTER_PAGE: (88 0.4706148282097649 . 0.3652618135376756)
In those societies of the ancient world in which slavery was the dominant relation of production, the parallel between the domestic animal and the slave appears to have been self-evident.
NOTER_PAGE: (88 0.7495479204339963 . 0.10600255427841636)
although the relations pastoralists establish with animals are quite different from those established by hunters, they rest, at a more fundamental level, on the same premise, namely that animals are, like human beings, endowed with powers of sentience and autonomous action which have either to be respected, as in hunting, or overcome through superior force, as in pastoralism.
NOTER_PAGE: (89 0.8155515370705244 . 0.243933588761175)
domestication of creatures that were once wild, should rather be described as a transition from trust to domination.
NOTER_PAGE: (90 0.10623869801084991 . 0.5140485312899107)
neither trust nor domination is in any sense more or less advanced than the other.
NOTER_PAGE: (90 0.4534358047016275 . 0.4655172413793104)
Trust, as I have shown, is a relation fraught with risk, tension and ambiguity.
NOTER_PAGE: (90 0.5045207956600362 . 0.6679438058748404)
The underside of trust, as Hallowell shows so clearly, is chronic anxiety and suspi- cion.
NOTER_PAGE: (90 0.5569620253164557 . 0.14559386973180077)
When hunters became pastoralists they began to relate to animals, and to one another, in different ways. But they were not taking the first steps on the road to modernity.
NOTER_PAGE: (90 0.6428571428571428 . 0.4310344827586207)
no essential difference between the ways one relates to humans and to non-human constituents of the environment.
NOTER_PAGE: (90 0.8340867992766726 . 0.19412515964240104)
transition from hunting to pastoralism led to the emergence, in place of egalitarian relations of sharing, of relations of dominance and subordination between herding leaders and their assistants
NOTER_PAGE: (91 0.10804701627486438 . 0.7624521072796935)
anthropology, as an intellectual product of the Western tradition, has sought to contain the damage by relativising the indigenous view and thereby neutralising the challenge it presents
NOTER_PAGE: (91 0.3318264014466546 . 0.5530012771392082)
Cultural Relativism
Making things, growing plants, raising animals and bringing up children
idea of production as making, I argue, is embedded in a grand narrative of the human transcendence of nature,
NOTER_PAGE: (92 0.59039759939985 . 0.1027542372881356)
basically just two ways of procuring a livelihood from the natural environment, conventionally denoted by the terms collection and production.
NOTER_PAGE: (92 0.8499624906226557 . 0.1461864406779661)
distinctively human: ‘The most that the animal can achieve is to collect; man produces, he prepares the means of life
NOTER_PAGE: (93 0.08852213053263316 . 0.3845338983050847)
The human, by contrast, always has an end in mind.
NOTER_PAGE: (93 0.22655663915978996 . 0.3315677966101695)
notion of food-production as the singular achievement of human agriculturalists and pastoralists has become part of the stock-in-trade of modern prehistory.
NOTER_PAGE: (93 0.6796699174793699 . 0.576271186440678)
decisive moment at which humanity transcended nature, and was set on the path of history.
NOTER_PAGE: (93 0.7651912978244562 . 0.7489406779661016)
Hunter-gatherers have a history, but theirs is a history that is written neither in the pages of documents nor upon the surface of the land.
NOTER_PAGE: (94 0.6594148537134283 . 0.1302966101694915)
NOTER_PAGE: (94 0.7621905476369093 . 0.423728813559322)
NOTER_PAGE: (94 0.8327081770442611 . 0.2616525423728814)
peoples of the past who were initially responsible for domesticating plants and animals must have had quite different ideas about what they were doing.
NOTER_PAGE: (94 0.8537134283570893 . 0.4661016949152542)
the essence of the kind of thought we call ‘Western’ is that it is founded in a claim to the subordination of nature by human powers of reason.
NOTER_PAGE: (95 0.22580645161290322 . 0.4470338983050847)
fulcrum of Marx’s theory of value, according to which it was the work of shaping up the material from its raw to its final state that bestowed value on what was already ‘given’ in nature.
NOTER_PAGE: (95 0.3308327081770443 . 0.13347457627118645)
such making is not the equivalent but the very opposite of production, just as artisanship is the opposite of agriculture.
NOTER_PAGE: (95 0.9047261815453864 . 0.4205508474576271)
The farmer, and for that matter the raiser of livestock, submits to a productive dynamic that is immanent in the natural world itself, rather than converting nature into an instrument to his own purpose.
NOTER_PAGE: (96 0.10502625656414104 . 0.3019067796610169)
NOTER_PAGE: (96 0.4013503375843961 . 0.3294491525423729)
NOTER_PAGE: (96 0.5708927231807952 . 0.4555084745762712)
Motherhood, however, also extends to a woman’s relations with the plants she grows in her garden. She has, as it were, two sets of offspring,
NOTER_PAGE: (97 0.3938484621155289 . 0.24470338983050846)
the forest is itself a huge garden, albeit an untidy one, and the relations between its constituents are governed by the same principles of domesticity that structure the human household, yet on a superhuman scale.
NOTER_PAGE: (97 0.6391597899474869 . 0.1906779661016949)
The antithesis of mbo is rømi. This latter term is used for things or powers that lie beyond the reach of human nurture.
NOTER_PAGE: (98 0.1582895723930983 . 0.4014830508474576)
at first glance, the terms mbo and rømi seem to have their more or less exact equivalent in our conventional notions of ‘wild’ and ‘domestic’
NOTER_PAGE: (98 0.22955738934733685 . 0.2584745762711864)
Completely absent from the Hagen conception, however, is the notion of a domestic environment ‘carved out’ from wild nature.
NOTER_PAGE: (98 0.2798199549887472 . 0.13135593220338984)
The child does not begin as rømi, and become mbo. It is mbo from the outset, by virtue of its planting within the field of human relationships.
NOTER_PAGE: (98 0.5888972243060765 . 0.2711864406779661)
maintenance of the village depends upon a continual inflow of vital force from the bush, which is worn 8 down and used up in the process.
NOTER_PAGE: (99 0.19429857464366093 . 0.4078389830508475)
the cultivated fields and gardens are sites of consumption rather than production, where vital force is used up.
NOTER_PAGE: (99 0.2970742685671418 . 0.583686440677966)
the farmer is called upon to assist in the animals’ labour much as a midwife assists at a birth. But the ultimate source of the ‘strength’ or ‘force’ (la fuerza) that enables people to work, animals to reproduce and crops to grow lies in the land itself.
NOTER_PAGE: (99 0.46886721680420107 . 0.576271186440678)
I believe this modern emphasis on production as making accounts for the special signif- icance that tends to be attached to the so-called ‘artificial selection’ of plants and animals
NOTER_PAGE: (100 0.2565641410352588 . 0.1292372881355932)
in many parts of the world, both in the past and still today, people are apparently engaged in the husbandry of plants and animals that do not differ appreciably from their wild counterparts.
NOTER_PAGE: (100 0.6039009752438109 . 0.6292372881355932)
does not literally make plants and animals, but rather establishes the environmental conditions for their growth and development.
NOTER_PAGE: (100 0.9032258064516129 . 0.7913135593220338)
growing plants and raising animals are not so different, in principle, from bringing up children.
NOTER_PAGE: (101 0.12603150787696923 . 0.3845338983050847)
‘the child grows into social maturity rather than being trained into it’
NOTER_PAGE: (101 0.27906976744186046 . 0.5773305084745762)
trees do not fit at all comfortably within the terms of the orthodox distinction between the wild and the domesticated, which may account for the curious fact that despite their manifest importance to people (as our Dogon example shows), they are all but absent from archaeological and anthropological discussions of the nature and origins of food production.
NOTER_PAGE: (101 0.6796699174793699 . 0.7076271186440678)
NOTER_PAGE: (102 0.417854463615904 . 0.21504237288135594)
NOTER_PAGE: (102 0.5026256564141035 . 0.2849576271186441)
The orthodox Western account, as we have seen, extends the idea of making from the domain of inanimate things to that of animate beings. I want to suggest, quite to the contrary, that the idea of growing might be extended in the reverse direction, from the animate to the inanimate. What we call ‘things’, too, are grown.
NOTER_PAGE: (102 0.8657164291072769 . 0.5921610169491526)
A circumpolar night's dream
is an organism a thing or a being?
NOTER_PAGE: (104 0.48762190547636913 . 0.4343220338983051)
think of the organism not as containing life, or expressing it, but as emergent within the life process itself.
NOTER_PAGE: (104 0.6106526631657915 . 0.2055084745762712)
build on the premise that all organisms, including human ones, are not things but beings.
NOTER_PAGE: (105 0.2805701425356339 . 0.5858050847457628)
NOTER_PAGE: (106 0.6271567891972993 . 0.1048728813559322)
NOTER_PAGE: (106 0.7456864216054013 . 0.5423728813559322)
what distinguishes the Thunder Bird from any ordinary hawk is nothing like what, for us, distinguishes the Wolf of Little Red Riding Hood from the wolf of the forest. The distinction is not between animals of fantasy and of fact, but rather between animals that are persons and animals that are not.
NOTER_PAGE: (107 0.5056264066016505 . 0.2330508474576271)
NOTER_PAGE: (109 0.13953488372093023 . 0.6048728813559322)
clothing does not cover up the body, it is a body
NOTER_PAGE: (109 0.2280570142535634 . 0.2584745762711864)
if I were to report, in all sincerity, having encountered such a character as Puck or Iron Maker in real life, I doubt whether much credence would be given to my claims. People would say that if I was not actually lying, then I must be suffering from delusions, leaving me incapable of telling fact from fantasy, or reality from dreams. Yet these are precisely the sorts of claims that Ojibwa make. Are they, then, lying or deluded?
NOTER_PAGE: (110 0.1072768192048012 . 0.5222457627118644)
willing suspension of disbelief.
NOTER_PAGE: (110 0.2940735183795949 . 0.475635593220339)
I once asked an old man: Are all the stones we see about us here alive? He reflected a long while and then replied, ‘No! But some are.’
NOTER_PAGE: (111 0.19429857464366093 . 0.1472457627118644)
the categorical distinction between animate and inanimate is not one that Ojibwa articulate themselves,
NOTER_PAGE: (111 0.3983495873968492 . 0.3453389830508475)
Animacy, in other words, is a property not of stones as such, but of their positioning within a relational field which includes persons as foci of power.
NOTER_PAGE: (112 0.2663165791447862 . 0.15148305084745764)
The nature of the things one encounters, their essence, is not given in advance but is revealed only ‘after-the-fact’,
NOTER_PAGE: (112 0.5708927231807952 . 0.3485169491525424)
This Ojibwa way of dealing with percep- tion is, as Black puts it, fundamentally antitaxonomic,
NOTER_PAGE: (112 0.6256564141035259 . 0.510593220338983)
If 8 we were to consider the sun in abstraction from its observed movement across the sky, then it would indeed appear to be a mere physical body, and its movement a mechanical displacement. But this is not how it is presented to us in immediate experience. Rather, the movement is as much a part of the way the sun is as my own habitual movements are of the way I am.
NOTER_PAGE: (113 0.5543885971492873 . 0.361228813559322)
living beings do not move upon the world, but move along with it.
NOTER_PAGE: (113 0.7111777944486122 . 0.6430084745762712)
‘the crucial test is experience’
NOTER_PAGE: (113 0.8312078019504876 . 0.24258474576271186)
NOTER_PAGE: (114 0.12378094523630909 . 0.21610169491525424)
knowledge does not lie in the accumulation of mental content. It is not by representing it in the mind that they get to know the world, but rather by moving around
NOTER_PAGE: (114 0.2250562640660165 . 0.21610169491525424)
NOTER_PAGE: (114 0.3150787696924231 . 0.13771186440677965)
NOTER_PAGE: (114 0.40210052513128286 . 0.2817796610169492)
forbidden under normal circumstances to speak of his experience
NOTER_PAGE: (114 0.46736684171042764 . 0.3093220338983051)
encouraged to think of dreams as hallucinations,
NOTER_PAGE: (115 0.6234058514628658 . 0.3485169491525424)
This is not to say that Ojibwa confuse dream experiences with those they have while wide awake. The difference is that in dreams, the vital essence of the person – the self – is afforded a degree of mobility, not only in space but also in time, normally denied in waking life. While the body of the sleeper is readily visible at some fixed location, the self may be roaming far afield
NOTER_PAGE: (115 0.8154538634658665 . 0.2913135593220339)
The dreaming mind, far from cutting its already tenuous and provisional connection with the real world, is able to penetrate that world to the point where mind and world become indistinguishable.
NOTER_PAGE: (116 0.19204801200300076 . 0.2341101694915254)
NOTER_PAGE: (116 0.46811702925731435 . 0.1239406779661017)
it makes no difference whether the boy was awake, day-dreaming or actually asleep. He still saw the bird, was moved to wonder by its presence, and remembered the encounter for the rest of his life.
NOTER_PAGE: (116 0.6939234808702176 . 0.5688559322033898)
Far from covering over a solid substrate of literal reality with layer upon layer of illusion, what dreams do is to penetrate beneath the surface of the world, to render it transparent, so that one can see into it with a clarity and vision that is not possible in ordinary life.
NOTER_PAGE: (116 0.8162040510127532 . 0.3834745762711864)
An old man and his wife are sitting in their tent, and a storm is raging outside. There is thunder and lightning. The thunder comes in a series of claps. The old man listens intently. Then he turns to his wife and asks, quite casually and in a matter-of-fact tone of voice, ‘Did you hear what was said?’ ‘No’, she replies, ‘I didn’t catch it’
NOTER_PAGE: (117 0.4703675918979745 . 0.2542372881355932)
NOTER_PAGE: (118 0.10502625656414104 . 0.5699152542372882)
this model does not posit the self in advance of the person’s entry into the world; rather, the self is constituted as a centre of agency and awareness in the process of its active engagement within an environment. Feeling, remembering, intending and speaking are all aspects of that engagement, and through it the self continually comes into being.
NOTER_PAGE: (118 0.6759189797449363 . 0.19385593220338984)
different view of speech, not as the outward expression of inner thoughts, but as one of the ways in which the self manifests its presence in the world. Thus when I speak or clap, I myself am not separate from the sound I produce – of my voice or the mutually percussive impact of my hands. These sounds are part of the way I am, they belong to my being as it issues forth into the environment. In other words, speech is not a mode of transmitting information or mental content; it is a way of being alive.
NOTER_PAGE: (119 0.5746436609152288 . 0.1281779661016949)
NOTER_PAGE: (120 0.2633158289572393 . 0.2966101694915254)
Responding to that presence with sensitivity and understanding is not therefore a matter of translation. It is more a matter of empathy.
NOTER_PAGE: (121 0.3171929824561403 . 0.33201189296333)
Animism, he writes, is ‘a kind of objectification of nature [which] endows natural beings not only with human dispositions, granting them the status of persons with human emotions and often the ability to talk, but also with social attributes – a hierarchy of positions, behaviours based on kinship, respect for certain norms of conduct’
NOTER_PAGE: (121 0.8182456140350877 . 0.13478691774033696)
Whereas animism takes the relational character of the world as an ontological a priori, against which the ‘naturalness’ of beings – the material forms in which they appear – stands out as unstable and problematic, naturalism takes it for granted that nature really exists, as an ontological domain of order and necessity where things are what they are, in themselves.
NOTER_PAGE: (122 0.263859649122807 . 0.11199207135777997)
place the mode of under- standing of Western science within the context of the primary existential condition, revealed in Ojibwa thought and practice, of being alive to the world.
NOTER_PAGE: (122 0.591578947368421 . 0.645193260654113)
I suggested that what the Ojibwa have arrived at is not an alternative science of nature but a poetics of dwelling. In the past, there has been a tendency to write off such poetics as the outpourings of a primitive mentality that has been superseded by the rise of the modern scientific worldview. My conclusion, to the contrary, is that scientific activity is always, and necessarily, grounded in a poetics of dwelling. Rather than sweeping it under the carpet, as an embarrassment, I believe this is something worth celebrating, and that doing so will also help us do better science.
NOTER_PAGE: (125 0.12350877192982455 . 0.13181367690782952)
Totemism, animism and the depiction of animals
NOTER_PAGE: (126 0.8165644171779142 . 0.16897746967071056)
association of clans with species is a corollary of a more fundamental set of linkages between people, land and ancestral beings.
NOTER_PAGE: (127 0.4553243574051407 . 0.3509075194468453)
NOTER_PAGE: (127 0.7625458996328028 . 0.4788245462402766)
NOTER_PAGE: (127 0.810281517747858 . 0.4520311149524633)
the powers that bring forth life, instead of being concentrated in the land itself, are rather distributed among the mani- fold beings that inhabit it. There is no power source, analogous to the totemic ancestors of Aboriginal cosmology, that subtends the life process itself.
NOTER_PAGE: (128 0.4192166462668298 . 0.5937770095073466)
People of course have to hunt (as well as gather) to secure a livelihood, but the actual pursuit of animals lacks cosmological significance.
NOTER_PAGE: (128 0.8665850673194614 . 0.27657735522904064)
In an animic system, on the other hand, hunting effects the circulation of vital force between humans and animals and thus contributes directly to the regeneration of the lifeworld of which both are part.
NOTER_PAGE: (129 0.1401468788249694 . 0.5877268798617113)
The connection, in other words, lies in the essential consubstantiality of members of the human group, and of the animal species, all of whom derive the lineaments of their being from the same place in the landscape in which is deposited the creativity of the kangaroo ancestor.
NOTER_PAGE: (129 0.34700122399020805 . 0.4727744165946413)
Ancestry, generation, substance, memory, land
Does not the conflation of the two terms, indigenous and aboriginal, merely perpetuate a thoroughly Eurocentric image of the precolonial world as a mosaic of cultures and territories that was already fixed in perpetuity before history began?
NOTER_PAGE: (147 0.4340490797546013 . 0.17256317689530684)
On what grounds can contemporary generations partake of the ‘originality’ of their predecessors?
NOTER_PAGE: (147 0.5915132924335379 . 0.19350180505415163)
NOTER_PAGE: (148 0.2121676891615542 . 0.22454873646209386)
both cultural knowledge and bodily substance are seen to undergo contin- uous generation in the context of an ongoing engagement with the land
NOTER_PAGE: (148 0.3133946830265849 . 0.2548736462093863)
it is in confronting the need to articulate their experience in an idiom compatible with the dominant discourses of the state that people are led to lay claim to indigenous status, in terms that neverthe- less systematically invert their own understandings.
NOTER_PAGE: (148 0.34918200408997957 . 0.5415162454873645)
formal attempts to define the indigenous can only be understood in the political context
NOTER_PAGE: (148 0.4350715746421268 . 0.2296028880866426)
an example of a way of thinking about what it means to be indigenous which, I believe, is symptomatic of more fundamental patterns of thought.
NOTER_PAGE: (148 0.612474437627812 . 0.25703971119133573)
THE GENEALOGICAL MODEL
NOTER_PAGE: (149 0.3057259713701432 . 0.13574007220216605)
NOTER_PAGE: (150 0.17433537832310841 . 0.41444043321299634)
Land is there to be occupied, but does not itself contribute to the constitution of its occupants. It therefore lies outside of history.
NOTER_PAGE: (150 0.2955010224948876 . 0.15884476534296027)
NOTER_PAGE: (150 0.7121676891615543 . 0.3487364620938628)
PART II: Dwelling
the dwelling perspective. By this I mean a perspective that treats the immersion of the organism-person in an environment or lifeworld as an inescapable condition of existence.
NOTER_PAGE: (168 0.3323108384458078 . 0.6534296028880866)
the world continually comes into being around the inhabitant, and its manifold constituents take on significance through their incorporation into a regular pattern of life activity.
NOTER_PAGE: (168 0.38241308793456036 . 0.09963898916967509)
Culture, perception and cognition
Take people from different backgrounds and place them in the same situation; they are likely to differ in what they make of it. Indeed such difference is something that every anthropologist experiences in the initial phases of fieldwork. But why should this be so? How do we account for it?
NOTER_PAGE: (172 0.3067484662576687 . 0.10685920577617328)
ECOLOGICAL PSYCHOLOGY
NOTER_PAGE: (181 0.130879345603272 . 0.14007220216606497)
perceptual activity consists not in the operation of the mind upon the bodily data of sense, but in the intentional movement of the whole being (indissolubly body and mind) in its environment.
NOTER_PAGE: (181 0.15950920245398775 . 0.7415162454873646)
for Gibson, sensations do not, as such, constitute the data for perception (Gibson 1979: 55). Rather, what the perceiver looks for are constancies underlying the continuous modulations of the sensory array as one moves from place to place.
NOTER_PAGE: (181 0.29754601226993865 . 0.1963898916967509)
to perceive an object or event is to perceive what it affords. Perhaps the most fundamental contribution of Gibson’s approach to perception lay in his insight that the information picked up by an agent in the context of practical activity specifies what are called the ‘affordances’ of objects and events in the environment
NOTER_PAGE: (181 0.6947852760736197 . 0.1335740072202166)
contrary to the axioms of cognitive anthropology, the communion of experience that lies at the heart of sociality does not depend upon the organisation of sensory data, initially private to each perceiver, in terms of an objective system of collective representations. Rather, sociality is given from the start, prior to the objectification of experience in cultural categories, in the direct, perceptual involvement of fellow participants in a shared environment
NOTER_PAGE: (182 0.6273006134969326 . 0.4353790613718411)
NOTER_PAGE: (183 0.4233128834355829 . 0.13935018050541514)
Building, dwelling, living: how animals and people make themselves at home in the world
The most fundamental thing about life is that it does not begin here or end there, but is always going on.
NOTER_PAGE: (187 0.39979550102249495 . 0.6433212996389891)
CONSTRUCTING ENVIRONMENTS AND MAKING WORLDS
NOTER_PAGE: (188 0.7827198364008181 . 0.10974729241877255)
The difference between the lodge and the house lies, I argued, not in the construction of the thing itself, but in the origination of the design that governs the construction process.
NOTER_PAGE: (190 0.26022494887525566 . 0.6433212996389891)
They are only being made, I claimed, when they are constructed in the imag- ination prior to their realisation in the material
NOTER_PAGE: (190 0.6063394683026585 . 0.2194945848375451)
Without altering the stone in any way, you have made a hammer out of it.
NOTER_PAGE: (190 0.7448875255623723 . 0.5703971119133574)
the stone was co-opted, rather than constructed, to become a hammer.
NOTER_PAGE: (190 0.8169734151329244 . 0.5913357400722021)
I concluded that ‘making is equivalent to the cultural ordering of nature – the inscription of ideal design upon the material world of things’ (Ingold 1989: 506). This statement, I confess, is now a source of considerable embarrassment.
NOTER_PAGE: (193 0.4877300613496933 . 0.21588447653429602)
THE BUILDING PERSPECTIVE
NOTER_PAGE: (193 0.5587934560327199 . 0.1299638989169675)
THE SEARCH FOR ORIGINS
NOTER_PAGE: (196 0.5582822085889572 . 0.10902527075812274)
THE DWELLING PERSPECTIVE
NOTER_PAGE: (200 0.26584867075664625 . 0.11046931407942237)
what does it take for a house to be a home
NOTER_PAGE: (200 0.5378323108384458 . 0.11046931407942237)
encompassed the whole manner in which one lives one’s life on the earth; thus ‘I dwell, you dwell’ is identical to ‘I am, you are’. Yet bauen has another sense: to preserve, to care for, or more specifically to cultivate or to till the soil. And then there is the third sense: to construct, to make something, to raise up an edifice.
NOTER_PAGE: (200 0.6779141104294479 . 0.5155234657039711)
‘We do not dwell because we have built, but we build and have built because we dwell, that is because we are dwellers . . . To build is in itself already to dwell . . . Only if we are capable of dwelling, only then can we build
NOTER_PAGE: (201 0.08793456032719837 . 0.23682310469314077)
THE HOUSE AS ORGANISM
NOTER_PAGE: (202 0.40950920245398775 . 0.10830324909747292)
The temporality of the landscape
Globes and spheres: the topology of environmentalism
To journey along a way of life: maps, wayfinding and navigation
INTRODUCTION
NOTER_PAGE: (234 0.3030812324929972 . 0.10047468354430379)
the native inhabitant may be unable to specify his location in space, in terms of any independent system of coordinates, and yet will still insist with good cause that he knows where he is.
NOTER_PAGE: (234 0.730532212885154 . 0.3647151898734177)
places do not have locations but histories. Bound
NOTER_PAGE: (234 0.7691876750700279 . 0.3552215189873418)
COGNITIVE MAPS
NOTER_PAGE: (235 0.286226318484383 . 0.13521330441070137)
wayfinding is understood as a skilled performance in which the traveller, whose powers of perception and action have been fine-tuned through previous experience, ‘feels his way’ towards his goal, continually adjusting his movements in response to an ongoing perceptual monitoring of his surroundings. What the first approach explains through positing an isomorphism between structures in the world and structures in the mind, the second explains as the unfolding of a field of relations established through the immersion of the actor-perceiver within a given environmental context.
NOTER_PAGE: (235 0.5381464413722479 . 0.3007953723788865)
NOTER_PAGE: (238 0.09267793138760881 . 0.2856109906001446)
WHAT IS A MAP ANYWAY?
NOTER_PAGE: (238 0.33640552995391704 . 0.11207519884309472)
NOTER_PAGE: (238 0.6789554531490015 . 0.30151843817787416)
the difference between the image and the map comes to hinge on the criterion of the indexicality or non-indexicality of its tokens.
NOTER_PAGE: (238 0.8530465949820788 . 0.15907447577729572)
NOTER_PAGE: (239 0.2626728110599078 . 0.13593637020968907)
what the map affords is a representation of things in space that is independent of any particular point of view.
NOTER_PAGE: (239 0.5074244751664106 . 0.13304410701373826)
NOTER_PAGE: (240 0.17716333845366103 . 0.28778018799710775)
The expert mariner has committed to memory an entire compendium of star courses, each unique to a particular pair of islands, and it is in this compendium, according to Gell, that his ‘map’ consists.
NOTER_PAGE: (240 0.43266769073220684 . 0.2588575560375994)
here is the paradox: actual maps are made to appear indexical with regard to cultural tradition only by a rendering of culture as non-indexical with regard to locality.
NOTER_PAGE: (241 0.08960573476702509 . 0.48590021691973967)
what maps index is movement, that the vision they embody is not local but regional, but that the ambition of modern cartography has been to convert this regional vision into a global one,
NOTER_PAGE: (241 0.22887864823348694 . 0.1764280549530007)
HOW TO SEE THE WORLD FROM EVERYWHERE AT ONCE
NOTER_PAGE: (241 0.3046594982078853 . 0.13449023861171366)
It is not a view from ‘up there’ rather than ‘down here’, but one taken along the multiple paths that make up a country, and along which people come and go in the practical conduct of life. Our perception of the environment as a whole, in short, is forged not in the ascent from a myopic, local perspective to a panoptic, global one, but in the passage from place to place, and in histories of movement and changing horizons along the way.
NOTER_PAGE: (242 0.4700460829493088 . 0.30441070137382503)
KNOWING AS YOU GO
NOTER_PAGE: (243 0.5965181771633384 . 0.13449023861171366)
difficulty in Turnbull’s argument. For while on the one hand, he insists that a common characteristic of all knowledge systems is their ‘localness’, he also argues, on the other, that what is critical to the growth and reproduction of any knowledge system is the work that goes into moving its diverse components – including practitioners, their know-how and skills, technical devices and standards of evaluation – from one local site of knowledge production to another
NOTER_PAGE: (243 0.8847926267281105 . 0.27476500361532896)
Much of the labour of science, Turnbull argues, lies in attempts to establish the connectivity and equivalence that would render procedures developed and results obtained in one local context applica- ble in another
NOTER_PAGE: (244 0.28008192524321557 . 0.20968908170643527)
‘all knowing is like travelling, like a journey between the parts of a matrix’ (1991: 35). So what is this matrix? It is, of course, a region in the sense defined above – that is, as the sum of journeys made.
NOTER_PAGE: (244 0.434715821812596 . 0.41793203181489513)
‘we go from one local knowledge to another rather than from universal theo- ries to their particular instantiations’
NOTER_PAGE: (244 0.6769073220686124 . 0.21402747650036152)
one of the most striking characteristics of the modern map is its elimination, or erasure, of the practices and itineraries that contributed to its production
NOTER_PAGE: (245 0.144905273937532 . 0.21691973969631237)
MAPPING IS NOT MAPMAKING
NOTER_PAGE: (246 0.38453661034306197 . 0.11207519884309472)
NOTER_PAGE: (246 0.7275985663082437 . 0.28705712219812)
regard mapping as the re-enactment, in narrative gesture, of the experience of moving from place to place within a region.
NOTER_PAGE: (247 0.6769073220686124 . 0.4786695589298626)
Undoubtedly the vast majority of maps that have ever been produced in human societies, like those of the Inuit, have been improvised on the spot within a particular dialogic or storytelling context, and without any intention for their preservation or use beyond that context.
NOTER_PAGE: (248 0.10752688172043011 . 0.6023138105567607)
In the course of producing such a map, the mapper takes his interlocutors on a tour of the country, and as he does so his moving hand, which may or may not hold an inscribing implement, traces out the paths taken and the sights or landmarks encountered along the way.
NOTER_PAGE: (248 0.24833589349718382 . 0.13159797541576282)
studies of native North American and Inuit maps have shown that they invariably rest on deictic principles: that is, they point to things, revealing aspects of how they look as one proceeds along a path of observation from ‘here’ to ‘there’
NOTER_PAGE: (248 0.3671274961597542 . 0.10773680404916847)
people continue to describe their environment, to themselves and others, by retracing the paths of movement they customarily take through it rather than by assigning each of its features to a fixed loca- tion in space.
NOTER_PAGE: (248 0.45622119815668205 . 0.2002892263195951)
‘written records were thought of and treated as reminders rather than representa- tions’
NOTER_PAGE: (248 0.7286226318484383 . 0.14967462039045554)
NOTER_PAGE: (250 0.14183307731694828 . 0.4287780187997108)
to edge art off the map is also to edge human actor-perceivers off the world,
NOTER_PAGE: (250 0.5913978494623656 . 0.42660882140274764)
WAYFINDING IS NOT NAVIGATION
NOTER_PAGE: (250 0.6845878136200717 . 0.10918293564714389)
‘Navigation’, writes Edwin Hutchins, ‘is a collection of techniques for answering a small number of questions, perhaps the most central of which is “Where am I?”’
NOTER_PAGE: (250 0.7122375832053252 . 0.10412147505422993)
according to Hutchins, one must possess some representation of space – a map – whether internal or external, inscribed in the mind or on a sheet of paper, within which every object or feature in one’s environment is assigned a determinate location. One has then to be able to establish a coherent set of correspondences between what is depicted on the map and what is visible in one’s surroundings.
NOTER_PAGE: (250 0.7818740399385561 . 0.4656543745480839)
Cognition in the Wild
insist, however, that reduced to its bare essentials, navigation is a cognitive task that all of us face all the time as we find our way about, whether at sea or on land.
NOTER_PAGE: (251 0.28110599078341014 . 0.4078091106290672)
Navigation (or map-using) is, I contend, as strange to the ordinary practices of wayfinding as is cartography (or mapmaking) to ordinary practices of mapping.
NOTER_PAGE: (251 0.8904249871991807 . 0.24439624005784527)
hard to imagine why we should find the navigator’s charts so baffling, or why his skills should be so specialised, if they were but analogues of cognitive structures and capacities that we use all the time.
NOTER_PAGE: (252 0.09216589861751152 . 0.1099060014461316)
For those who know a country, in short, the answers to such basic questions as ‘Where am I?’ and ‘Which way should I go?’ are found in narratives of past movement.
NOTER_PAGE: (252 0.7132616487455197 . 0.1301518438177874)
PATHS, FLOWS AND THE PASSAGE OF TIME
NOTER_PAGE: (253 0.2345110087045571 . 0.13304410701373826)
‘the theory of reversible occlusion’ (1979: 198). In brief, the theory states that one knows the way in terms of the specific order in which the surfaces of the environment come into or pass out of sight as one proceeds along a path.
NOTER_PAGE: (253 0.34715821812596004 . 0.1301518438177874)
NOTER_PAGE: (253 0.7962109575012801 . 0.6579898770788142)
the path is specified not as a sequence of point-indexical images, but as the coming-into- sight and passing-out-of-sight of variously contoured and textured surfaces.
NOTER_PAGE: (254 0.09114183307731695 . 0.10701373825018076)
once it is recognised that the wayfinder’s multi- sensory monitoring is of flows, not images, and that flows specify paths and not spatial locations, Gell’s objections to the idea of mapless practical mastery fall away.
NOTER_PAGE: (255 0.17562724014336917 . 0.48590021691973967)
The alleged bearing of the etak does not enter into any numerical computation. Rather, pointing to the etak is the mariner’s way of indicating where he is in terms of the temporal unfolding of the voyage as a whole
NOTER_PAGE: (255 0.4700460829493088 . 0.20968908170643527)
THE WORLD HAS NO SURFACE
NOTER_PAGE: (255 0.7147977470558116 . 0.1294287780187997)
the world is apprehended from within. One makes one’s way through it, not over or across it.
NOTER_PAGE: (256 0.141321044546851 . 0.7809110629067245)
In short for its manifold inhabitants, journeying along their respective ways of life, the world itself has no surface.
NOTER_PAGE: (256 0.3671274961597542 . 0.2046276211135213)
If a map consists of a network of interconnected lines, each corresponding to a path of movement through the world, there is no necessary reason why these lines should be inscribed on a surface. One could think of the gesturing hand, in mapping, as a weaving hand rather than a drawing hand, and of the result as something more akin to a cat’s cradle than a graph.
NOTER_PAGE: (256 0.5028161802355351 . 0.16775126536514823)
one could construct a route map for the London Underground out of stiff wire, soldered at the intersections, and it would serve just as well as the conventional printed versions. The fact that the map is generally reproduced on paper is a matter of obvious practical conven- ience, but not of logical necessity. The meaning of the map lies entirely in its routes and intersections, whereas the paper surface has no significance whatsoever.
NOTER_PAGE: (256 0.6103430619559652 . 0.6912509038322487)
CONCLUSION
NOTER_PAGE: (257 0.08704557091653865 . 0.1381055676066522)
NOTER_PAGE: (257 0.1863799283154122 . 0.3658712942877802)
The Map Is Not the Territory
to suggest that what is excluded in the cartographic reduction amounts, in Monmonier’s words, to a ‘fog of detail’ – is perverse, to say the least (Wood 1992: 76). For it is no less than the stuff of life itself.
NOTER_PAGE: (257 0.34357398873527906 . 0.2841648590021692)
Stop, look and listen! Vision, hearing and human movement
perception is not an ‘inside-the head’ operation, performed upon the raw material of sensation, but takes place in circuits that cross-cut the boundaries between brain, body and world.
NOTER_PAGE: (259 0.1612590799031477 . 0.8057455540355677)
vision and hearing are radically opposed, as different as is standing on the river bank, watching the water flow by, from being tossed in with the current.
NOTER_PAGE: (259 0.5907990314769975 . 0.37688098495212036)
So too, Heidegger would have said, we hear the train before the noise it makes. But this view is not easily reconciled with everyday experience.
NOTER_PAGE: (260 0.14043583535108958 . 0.4062927496580027)
Light and sound are, in essence, the undersides of the experiences of seeing and hearing respectively.
NOTER_PAGE: (260 0.45036319612590797 . 0.4021887824897401)
they are virtually indistinguishable: vision is a kind of hearing, and vice versa. This argument eventually leads me to reject the thesis that attributes the dominance of objective thinking in the West to an obsession with the eye.
NOTER_PAGE: (260 0.611138014527845 . 0.4521203830369357)
VISION OBJECTIFIES, SOUND PERSONIFIES
NOTER_PAGE: (260 0.763680387409201 . 0.11080711354309165)
NOTER_PAGE: (260 0.8164648910411623 . 0.3652530779753762)
the denigration of vision is as ancient as is its elevation to the top of the hierarchy of the senses.
NOTER_PAGE: (261 0.7108958837772397 . 0.5410396716826266)
THE WRITTEN WORD AND THE SOUNDS OF SPEECH
NOTER_PAGE: (262 0.2179176755447942 . 0.11149110807113544)
In his influential study, The Gutenberg Galaxy, Marshall McLuhan (1962) argued that the invention of the printing press ushered in an entirely new era in the history of human culture, marked by the absolute dominance of the eye, and with it a bias towards a way of thinking that is objective and analytic, and that follows a linear path of explicit logical connections.
NOTER_PAGE: (263 0.5699757869249394 . 0.15663474692202461)
one of McLuhan’s associates, Walter Ong, sought to derive all the essen- tial characteristics of ‘orally based thought and expression’ from the features that distinguish hearing from vision. Oral culture, he claimed, is aggregating, harmonic and holistic rather than dissecting, analytic and atomistic; concrete and situationally specific rather than abstract and context-independent; and focused on persons rather than things.
NOTER_PAGE: (263 0.7656174334140435 . 0.26880984952120385)
Orality and Literacy
It is in his contention that the listener in a ‘primarily oral’ culture hears words as sound, rather than as images shaped in sound, that Ong takes issue with Saussure
NOTER_PAGE: (264 0.3476997578692494 . 0.10259917920656635)
VISION AND HEARING IN ANTHROPOLOGY
NOTER_PAGE: (264 0.5254237288135594 . 0.1094391244870041)
McLuhan, Carpenter and Ong effectively laid the foundations for a currently vibrant field of inquiry that has come to be known as the anthropology of the senses
NOTER_PAGE: (265 0.0910411622276029 . 0.16347469220246238)
ku-mba, in the Suyá language, translates not only as ‘to hear’ but also as ‘to understand’ and ‘to know’. It is the ability to ‘hear-understand-know’ well that defines the person as a fully social being.
NOTER_PAGE: (266 0.10702179176755448 . 0.11285909712722297)
The sense of sight, to the contrary, is associated in Suyá thinking with morally delinquent, anti-social tendencies.
NOTER_PAGE: (266 0.1907990314769976 . 0.19288645690834472)
The Umeda, like many other peoples of Papua New Guinea, inhabit an environment of dense, and virtually unbroken forest, in which things are visible only at close range, normally within a few tens of metres. Such an environment, Gell argues, ‘imposes a reorganisation of sensibility’, giving pride of place to hearing, along with smell (Gell 1995: 235). Thus out hunting, Umeda walk with their eyes to the ground, listening for game instead of looking for it,
NOTER_PAGE: (266 0.36803874092009686 . 0.13269493844049246)
THE ANTHROPOLOGY OF THE SENSES: A FIRST CRITIQUE
NOTER_PAGE: (266 0.7365617433414043 . 0.10875512995896033)
these distinctions may reflect more upon the preconceptions of anthropological analysts
NOTER_PAGE: (267 0.12445520581113802 . 0.17305061559507523)
The true ‘seer’ of the Western tradition is the blind prophet: in Seeger’s words, ‘one who physically cannot see’
NOTER_PAGE: (267 0.34818401937046006 . 0.22503419972640218)
In the cosmology of the Yup’ik Eskimos, according to Anne Fienup-Riordan, ‘vision was an act constituting knowledge, and witnessing was a potentially creative act’ (1994: 316). The Eskimo cosmos, it transpires, teems with ever-watchful eyes.
NOTER_PAGE: (267 0.8837772397094431 . 0.3228454172366621)
Yet to the extent that he depends on powers of vision rather than hearing, the Inuit hunter does not, in consequence, find his relation with the world turned inside out. He remains, like his Umeda counterpart, at the centre of a dynamic cosmos, caught up in the process of its perpetual generation. Beings do not, all at once, appear to him inert and thinglike, nor does the hunter feel himself any more an observer, or any less a participant.
NOTER_PAGE: (268 0.5065375302663438 . 0.11149110807113544)
what is at stake is not the priority of vision over hearing, but the understanding of vision itself. Evidently, the primacy of vision cannot be held to account for the objectification of the world. Rather the reverse; it is through its co-option in the service of a peculiarly modern project of objectification that vision has been reduced to a faculty of pure, disinterested reflection, whose role is merely to deliver up ‘things’ to a transcendent consciousness.
NOTER_PAGE: (268 0.6092009685230024 . 0.5403556771545828)
very narrow and impoverished concept of vision to which its enlist- ment in the project of modernity has brought us.
NOTER_PAGE: (268 0.7990314769975787 . 0.29958960328317374)
we know what it means to hear sound but have effectively lost touch with the experience of light.
NOTER_PAGE: (268 0.8547215496368039 . 0.2893296853625171)
THE OPTICS OF DESCARTES
NOTER_PAGE: (269 0.08426150121065375 . 0.1347469220246238)
in the Western philosophical tradition, it is above all to touch rather than hearing that sight has been compared.
NOTER_PAGE: (269 0.36077481840193704 . 0.5595075239398085)
In defence of Descartes, it is important to recognise two aspects of this account which are often overlooked. First, it was plain to him that perception – whether visual or tactile – depended on movement. Were there no movement of the body and its sensory organs relative to the environment, nothing would be perceived. Ironically, this point has been lost in much of the subsequent psychology of vision, only to be rediscovered by advocates of an ecological approach to visual perception who adopt an explicitly anti-Cartesian stance.
NOTER_PAGE: (269 0.7980629539951574 . 0.5683994528043775)
Descartes did not, as is commonly supposed, argue that the function of the eyes is to establish internal representations of external objects,
NOTER_PAGE: (270 0.09007263922518159 . 0.11080711354309165)
As a purely cognitive faculty, vision can also work upon the data of touch. Equipped with a stick, or even with bare hands, the blind can see! So can sighted people, walking without a light on a pitch dark night
NOTER_PAGE: (270 0.43825665859564167 . 0.5697674418604651)
vision, now conceived as an exclusively intellectual achievement, is no longer conditioned in any way by the embodied experience of inhabiting an illuminated world.
NOTER_PAGE: (270 0.5050847457627119 . 0.46785225718194257)
the eyes, that look but cannot see, hand over to the ‘I’, the Cartesian cogito, who sees but cannot look.
NOTER_PAGE: (270 0.6944309927360774 . 0.10807113543091655)
the superiority of vision over touch is not that of one sense over another, but that of cognition over sensation.
NOTER_PAGE: (270 0.7307506053268765 . 0.5458276333789329)
ON THE MEANING OF LIGHT
NOTER_PAGE: (270 0.8203389830508475 . 0.11012311901504787)
Questions about the meaning of light, as of sound, are surely wrongly posed if they force us to choose between regarding light and sound as either physical or mental phenomena. They are wrongly posed because they continue to regard the organs of sense as gateways between an external, physical world and an internal world of mind.
NOTER_PAGE: (272 0.6246973365617433 . 0.23119015047879615)
Hans Jonas
NOTER_PAGE: (273 0.5956416464891041 . 0.13269493844049246)
The distinctiveness of sight, for Jonas, lies in three properties that are unique to this sensory modality: namely, simultaneity, neutralisation and distance
NOTER_PAGE: (273 0.625181598062954 . 0.1320109439124487)
what Jonas calls neutralisation, lies in the disengagement between the perceiver and the seen.
NOTER_PAGE: (274 0.2314769975786925 . 0.38645690834473323)
James Gibson
NOTER_PAGE: (275 0.09200968523002422 . 0.13611491108071136)
it is difficult to see how ‘manifestations of light’ can possibly be distinguished from ‘light as such’ without resorting to a highly reductive notion of what light actually is.
NOTER_PAGE: (277 0.3138014527845036 . 0.4719562243502052)
Maurice Merleau-Ponty
NOTER_PAGE: (277 0.5254237288135594 . 0.13406292749658003)
Do you have the impression that you are staring out upon the world through a hole (or perhaps two holes) in the front of your head? Is it as though you were looking through the windows of your unlit house, having opened the shutters?15 Far from it. Rather, it seems that you are out there yourself, shamelessly mingling with all you see, and flitting around like an agile spirit from one place to another as the focus of your attention shifts. It is as if the walls and ceiling of your house had simply vanished, leaving you out in the open. In short, you experience seeing not as seeing out, but as being out
NOTER_PAGE: (278 0.7312348668280871 . 0.21203830369357046)
vision ‘is the means given me for being absent from myself
NOTER_PAGE: (279 0.1089588377723971 . 0.2387140902872777)
we have progressed from a notion of vision as a mode of speculation, to one of vision as a mode of participation, and finally to one of vision as a mode of being.
NOTER_PAGE: (280 0.7326876513317191 . 0.18467852257181944)
THE HEARING EYE AND THE SEEING EAR
NOTER_PAGE: (281 0.21937046004842614 . 0.1354309165526676)
close parallels between the way Zuckerkandl speaks of the musical experience of sound, and the way Merleau-Ponty speaks of the painterly experience of light. These experiences, it turns out, are virtually identical.
NOTER_PAGE: (281 0.3525423728813559 . 0.2756497948016416)
the kind of opening up to the world that Merleau-Ponty calls seeing is more or less identical to that which Zuckerkandl calls hearing.
NOTER_PAGE: (282 0.6968687541638907 . 0.29350893697083724)
recognise that sound is no more a physical impulse that arrives from outside than it is a purely mental, ‘inside the head’ phenomenon. Indeed everything we have said about light applies to sound also.
NOTER_PAGE: (283 0.12391738840772819 . 0.6030103480714958)
I take it that the flight of most birds, at least at a distance, must be silent . . . Yet it appears audible, each species creating a different ‘eye-music’, from the nonchalant melancholy of seagulls to the staccato flitting of birds.
NOTER_PAGE: (283 0.3684210526315789 . 0.1599247412982126)
the eyes and ears should not be understood as separate keyboards for the registration of sensation but as organs of the body as a whole, in whose movement, within an environment, the activity of perception consists.
NOTER_PAGE: (283 0.6615589606928715 . 0.2634054562558796)
NOTER_PAGE: (284 0.6955363091272485 . 0.10724365004703669)
THE SENSORY EXPERIENCE OF BLIND AND DEAF PEOPLE
NOTER_PAGE: (284 0.8034643570952699 . 0.10912511759172154)
not, however, supported by the testimony of blind and deaf people themselves. These people do not feel that their experience of the world is any less complete, or has any less integrity, than that of anyone else. In this respect it is quite unlike the experience of normally sighted and hearing persons, on finding themselves suddenly but temporarily blinded or deafened.
NOTER_PAGE: (285 0.40173217854763493 . 0.4336782690498589)
aural perception actually deteriorates when it is not oriented 8 by vision,
NOTER_PAGE: (285 0.5556295802798135 . 0.1975540921919097)
mistakes a heightened sensitivity to specific movements – aural or gestural – which are critical for the interpretation of what is going on for a general enhancement of the sense as a whole.
NOTER_PAGE: (285 0.5769487008660893 . 0.5870178739416745)
not like a round cake from which a substantial slice has been cut out. It is more like a smaller cake
NOTER_PAGE: (285 0.6968687541638907 . 0.42144873000940736)
Being blind
NOTER_PAGE: (286 0.22051965356429049 . 0.11006585136406398)
The perception of the blind person, dependent as it is on touch and hearing, is fundamentally suspended in the current of time. Visual space is presented to the sighted all at once, but tactile space has to be assembled by the blind, bit by bit, through a repetitive and time-consuming exploration with the fingers.
NOTER_PAGE: (286 0.2618254497001999 . 0.26904985888993416)
Acoustic space is similarly temporal. Unlike the objects of touch, however, which can always be touched again, the manifold inhabitants of acoustic space have an ephemeral nature, passing in and out of existence along with the sounds they make.
NOTER_PAGE: (286 0.346435709526982 . 0.15145813734713076)
for the blind person, the voice or handshake comes from nowhere. One has the feeling of being grasped or accosted, unable either to resist or to choose one’s assailant
NOTER_PAGE: (286 0.4870086608927382 . 0.33490122295390407)
‘The intermittent nature of the acoustic world’, Hull writes, ‘is one of its most striking features’
NOTER_PAGE: (286 0.5409726848767489 . 0.5296331138287864)
when it is raining. For the sounds of rain- drops, which are perceived to come not from any particular point but from all quarters at once, reveal in every detail the surfaces on which they fall.
NOTER_PAGE: (286 0.698201199200533 . 0.49764816556914393)
Rain does for the blind what sunshine does for the sighted,
NOTER_PAGE: (286 0.8514323784143905 . 0.4957666980244591)
in Hull’s experience matters are not that simple. For him the face is not a mask but is as intimately bound up with the life and identity of the self as is the voice.
NOTER_PAGE: (287 0.3697534976682212 . 0.21730950141110067)
you can hear your own voice whereas you cannot see your own face.
NOTER_PAGE: (287 0.45436375749500335 . 0.2831608654750706)
It requires a real effort of will, if you are blind, to remind yourself that you can still be seen
NOTER_PAGE: (287 0.7308461025982679 . 0.4684854186265287)
blindness results – at least in Hull’s experience – in an overwhelming feeling of distance and withdrawal. ‘People’, as he puts it, ‘become mere sounds’, and ‘sounds are abstract’ (1997: 21, 48). For him, quite contrary to conventional wisdom, vision personifies, whereas sound objectifies.
NOTER_PAGE: (287 0.7808127914723518 . 0.6368767638758231)
the clear distinction that sighted people are inclined to make between touch and hearing may in fact be a consequence of vision,
NOTER_PAGE: (289 0.0966022651565623 . 0.20602069614299154)
NOTER_PAGE: (289 0.1758827448367755 . 0.3339604891815616)
seems probable that even sighted people, albeit unawares, are significantly guided by echolocation or ‘facial vision’ (Ihde 1976: 67–70). They simply do not pay any attention to it.
NOTER_PAGE: (289 0.2971352431712192 . 0.13640639698965193)
Being deaf
NOTER_PAGE: (289 0.44103930712858097 . 0.13452492944496708)
deafness is never absolute
NOTER_PAGE: (289 0.5869420386409061 . 0.3236124176857949)
I have to say that I am not convinced by the implied distinction between real and imaginary sound. For even the sounds that people with normal hearing routinely describe as real are no less phenomena of lived experience, and it is perfectly clear from Wright’s description of vision-hearing that the sounds he sees are, for him, every bit as vivid as are the sounds that other people hear, for them.
NOTER_PAGE: (290 0.3491005996002665 . 0.24459078080903104)
even for the aurally unimpaired, hearing is critically guided by the ‘antennae’ of sight. And it fits with Hull’s observation that when people go blind, their hearing does not improve but rather deteriorates
NOTER_PAGE: (290 0.5409726848767489 . 0.5174035747883349)
Recall that for Ong, people in a primarily oral culture hear words not as things, as though they were looking at them, but as sound. Similarly for deaf signers, gestures are movements to be watched, not objects to be looked at
NOTER_PAGE: (290 0.8860759493670887 . 0.12888052681091253)
McLuhan and Ong, of course, were above all concerned to contrast the properties of speech and writing. Their mistake, as should now have become clear, was to imagine that these contrasting properties could be deduced from the differences between hearing and vision.
NOTER_PAGE: (291 0.31245836109260494 . 0.15804327375352775)
The trace of a gesture, such as the calligrapher’s brush stroke, may be apprehended as a movement in just the same way as the gesture itself. In this, the reader’s eye follows the trace as it would follow the trajectory of the hand that made it. The written word is perceived as a thing only when it is read not as the trace of a visible gesture but as the representation of a vocal one.
NOTER_PAGE: (291 0.4170552964690207 . 0.13828786453433678)
THE INTERCHANGEABILITY OF VISUAL AND AUDITORY PERCEPTION
NOTER_PAGE: (291 0.6842105263157895 . 0.13076199435559738)
Stravinsky argues passionately for the former view. ‘I have always had a horror’, he writes, ‘of listening to music with my eyes shut, with nothing for them to do. The sight of the gestures and movements of the various parts of the body producing the music is fundamentally necessary if it is to be grasped in all its fullness’
NOTER_PAGE: (292 0.2631578947368421 . 0.3584195672624647)
NOTER_PAGE: (292 0.6588940706195869 . 0.19567262464722485)
The cosmos itself (ella) – sentient, knowing and responsive – was conceived as an immense eye, but it was one that could hear as well as see. It could also smell.
NOTER_PAGE: (293 0.1072618254497002 . 0.3264346190028222)
The knowledge that the eye of ella was watching, and that human activities were visible to the spirit world, controlled every aspect of everyday Yup’ik life.
NOTER_PAGE: (293 0.1758827448367755 . 0.6406396989651929)
interpret Seeger’s observation that among the Suyá, another Amazonian people, visual designs such as weaving patterns are seen acoustically. On learning such a design, they say ‘It is in my ear’
NOTER_PAGE: (296 0.5916055962691539 . 0.4280338664158043)
THE ANTHROPOLOGY OF THE SENSES: A SECOND CRITIQUE
NOTER_PAGE: (296 0.6675549633577615 . 0.10630291627469426)
the reduction to vision, in the West, has been accompanied by a second reduction, namely the reduction of vision. One cannot escape this reduction, inherent in the rhetoric of visualism, simply by erecting an antivisualism in its place
NOTER_PAGE: (297 0.625582944703531 . 0.39604891815616183)
a representationalist theory of knowledge, according to which people draw on the raw material of bodily sensation to build up an internal picture of what the world ‘out there’ is like, on the basis of models or schemata received through their education in a particular tradition.
NOTER_PAGE: (297 0.8540972684876749 . 0.43273753527751646)
Whether the mode of engagement with the environment of greatest practical importance to people is looking, listening, or touching, or some amalgam of these, is immaterial. What is important, so far as the ‘cross-cultural exploration of sensory orders’ is concerned, is that the meanings and understandings of the world gained through perceptual activity are expressed symbol- ically by way of metaphors drawn from one or another domain of sensory experience
NOTER_PAGE: (298 0.5369753497668222 . 0.6839134524929446)
as the level of analysis shifts from the individual to society as a whole, so the domain that is ‘mapped’ is no longer of bodily but of conceptual space. Instead of tracing a set metonymical connections between the sense organs and regions of the brain, the ‘cultural map’ establishes a system of metaphorical correspondences between the material realm of sensory experience and the ideal realm of mental representations.
NOTER_PAGE: (299 0.608927381745503 . 0.22483537158984007)
EPILOGUE
NOTER_PAGE: (300 0.7768154563624251 . 0.1147695202257761)
as though vision had been compelled to take on the mantle of a particular cognitive style, and all the virtues and vices that go with it.
NOTER_PAGE: (301 0.5423051299133911 . 0.17497648165569143)
one would have to show that seeing in actual practice, rather than as imagined by philosophers, harboured within itself a tendency towards reification
NOTER_PAGE: (301 0.6788807461692206 . 0.5663217309501412)
PART III: Skill
NOTER_PAGE: (304 0.4883411059293804 . 0.2831608654750706)
the transition, in the history of human technicity, from the hand-tool to the machine, is not from the simple to the complex, but is rather tantamount to the withdrawal of the producer, in person, from the centre to the periphery of the productive process.
NOTER_PAGE: (304 0.6608927381745503 . 0.19379115710254)
NOTER_PAGE: (305 0.41972018654230514 . 0.32455315145813735)
THE TECHNICAL AND THE MECHANICAL
NOTER_PAGE: (309 0.3037974683544304 . 0.1420507996237065)
Just occasionally, tekhnē and logos were combined in classical literature to denote the art of reason, or the skill involved in rhetorical debate. But in contemporary usage the meaning of technology is just the reverse: namely, the rational principles that govern the construction of artefacts – or more simply, the reason of art rather than the art of reason. In this sense, the term did not come into regular use until well into the seventeenth century
NOTER_PAGE: (309 0.7275149900066622 . 0.691439322671684)
The thing, we say, is virtually ‘conceived’ in advance of its realisation in practice. According to one view, these phases of design and construction correspond to the separate provinces of engineering and technology respectively
NOTER_PAGE: (310 0.5169886742171885 . 0.2285983066792098)
the architect, classically a ‘master-builder’, is now a creator of structures that are left to the industry to put up.
NOTER_PAGE: (310 0.6595602931379081 . 0.444967074317968)
Where excellence in the one field is attributed to genius, in the other it is attributed to expertise. Thus, constituted by its opposition to design, technique is reduced to the ‘merely technical’, and ultimately to the mechanical.
NOTER_PAGE: (310 0.8127914723517655 . 0.464722483537159)
THE DEFINITION OF TECHNOLOGY
NOTER_PAGE: (311 0.7341772151898734 . 0.13546566321730952)
NOTER_PAGE: (312 0.48634243837441704 . 0.2605832549388523)
For other writers, technology is effectively equivalent to the field of operation of human labour, together with the products to which it gives rise.
NOTER_PAGE: (312 0.6622251832111925 . 0.1317027281279398)
NOTER_PAGE: (313 0.4530313124583611 . 0.6218250235183443)
technology might be considered a human universal, ‘roughly characterized as the intersection of practical knowledge and ideology’
NOTER_PAGE: (313 0.5216522318454364 . 0.19379115710254)
a necessary first-step is surely to separate out the components of purpose, knowledge, activity and artefacts that are implicated in productive work.
NOTER_PAGE: (314 0.2111925383077948 . 0.3010348071495767)
OBJECT, PROCESS, KNOWLEDGE AND VOLITION
NOTER_PAGE: (314 0.3271152564956696 . 0.11288805268109126)
NOTER_PAGE: (315 0.6409060626249168 . 0.13640639698965193)
MOTORS, TRANSMITTERS AND WORKING PARTS
NOTER_PAGE: (317 0.6588940706195869 . 0.1458137347130762)
THE COMPLETE MACHINE
NOTER_PAGE: (319 0.475016655562958 . 0.13076199435559738)
MACHINES AND ANIMALS
NOTER_PAGE: (321 0.8494337108594271 . 0.13358419567262464)
MANUFACTURE AND MACHINOFACTURE
NOTER_PAGE: (323 0.5829447035309794 . 0.14016933207902163)
Society, nature and the concept of technology
NOTER_PAGE: (329 0.5401350337584396 . 0.15783898305084745)
NOTER_PAGE: (330 0.16879219804951237 . 0.1059322033898305)
NOTER_PAGE: (330 0.43360840210052515 . 0.13241525423728814)
conflation of the technical with the mechanical, a conflation that lies at the very core of the modern concept of technology.
NOTER_PAGE: (330 0.5416354088522131 . 0.23622881355932204)
technique is embedded in, and inseparable from, the experience of particular subjects in the shaping of particular things. In this respect it stands in sharp contrast to technology, which consists in a knowledge of objective prin- ciples of mechanical functioning, whose validity is completely independent both of the subjective identity of its human carriers and of the specific contexts of its application.
NOTER_PAGE: (330 0.7344336084021006 . 0.461864406779661)
commonly supposed that where there are techniques there must be technology, for if skill lies in the effective application of knowledge, there must be knowledge to apply (Layton). I believe this view to be mistaken.
NOTER_PAGE: (331 0.21380345086271568 . 0.2521186440677966)
NOTER_PAGE: (331 0.3150787696924231 . 0.3845338983050847)
THE TECHNICAL AND THE SOCIAL
NOTER_PAGE: (332 0.21605401350337586 . 0.11122881355932203)
NOTER_PAGE: (332 0.7291822955738935 . 0.1292372881355932)
in hunting and gathering societies, the forces of produc- tion are deeply embedded in the matrix of social relations. That is to say, the ‘correspondence’ between technical forces and social relations is not external but internal, or in other words, the technical is one aspect of the social.
NOTER_PAGE: (333 0.7134283570892723 . 0.4110169491525424)
NOTER_PAGE: (334 0.5416354088522131 . 0.10911016949152542)
Work, time and industry
TASK-ORIENTATION
NOTER_PAGE: (338 0.8364591147786947 . 0.10911016949152542)
work is life, and any distinctions one might make within the course of life would be not between work and non-work, but between different fields of activity, such as farming, cooking, child-minding, weaving, and so on.
NOTER_PAGE: (339 0.17779444861215304 . 0.2997881355932203)
The Nuer have no expression equivalent to ‘time’ in our language, and they cannot, therefore, speak of time as though it were something which passes, can be wasted, saved, and so forth. I do not think that they ever experience the same feeling of fighting against time or of having to co-ordinate activities with an abstract passage of time, because their points of reference are mainly the activities themselves, which are of a leisurely character. Events follow a logical order, but they are not controlled by an abstract system, there being no autonomous points of reference to which activities have to conform with precision. Nuer are fortunate.
NOTER_PAGE: (339 0.5221305326331583 . 0.15360169491525424)
a task-orientation in such societies, an orientation in which both work and time are intrinsic to the conduct of life itself, and cannot be separated or abstracted from it.
NOTER_PAGE: (339 0.8169542385596399 . 0.2764830508474576)
in Medieval England, duration could be expressed by how long it took to cook an egg, say a prayer, or (apparently) to have a pee – though this latter time-span, known as ‘pissing while’, does seem ‘a somewhat arbitrary measurement’ (Thompson 1967: 58).
NOTER_PAGE: (340 0.2805701425356339 . 0.2976694915254237)
NOTER_PAGE: (341 0.3360840210052513 . 0.4502118644067797)
THE TEMPORAL LOGIC OF CAPITALIST PRODUCTION
NOTER_PAGE: (341 0.4763690922730683 . 0.13453389830508475)
‘Mature industrial societies of all varieties are marked . . . by a clear demarcation between “work” and “life”’ (1967:). Of course he does not mean that workers are not alive when they work.
NOTER_PAGE: (341 0.5423855963990998 . 0.4036016949152542)
With industrial capitalism, labour becomes a commodity measured out in units of time, goods become commodities measured out in units of money; since labour produces goods, so much time yields so much money, and time spent in idleness is equivalent to so much money lost. The result is not only a demarcation between work (time that yields money) and leisure (time that uses it up), but also a characteristic attitude to time as something to be husbanded. Thompson calls this attitude ‘time-thrift’
NOTER_PAGE: (343 0.4013503375843961 . 0.3241525423728814)
TASKS, LABOUR AND LEISURE
NOTER_PAGE: (343 0.5446361590397599 . 0.13347457627118645)
TIME AND EXPERIENCE IN THE HOUSEHOLD AND THE WORKPLACE
NOTER_PAGE: (345 0.7569392348087022 . 0.13453389830508475)
First, the distinction falls – or at least used to fall – to some extent along lines of gender and generation, with women and children more committed to task-oriented time and men more committed to clock time. In the past, an obvious indication of this was that men, and not women and children, carried clocks or watches. If a woman or child wanted to know what the time was by the clock, they had to ask a man.
NOTER_PAGE: (346 0.350337584396099 . 0.3781779661016949)
Secondly, there can be scheduling conflicts between the two kinds of time which can cause quite severe disruptions within the household.
NOTER_PAGE: (346 0.4373593398349587 . 0.3972457627118644)
despite Marx’s claim to the contrary, the worker does not cease to dwell in the workplace. He is ‘at home’ there. But home is often a profoundly uncomfortable place to be.
NOTER_PAGE: (347 0.3158289572393098 . 0.3040254237288136)
THE LIFE AND TIMES OF LOCOMOTIVE DRIVERS
NOTER_PAGE: (348 0.8642160540135034 . 0.1048728813559322)
NOTER_PAGE: (349 0.26406601650412603 . 0.3633474576271186)
By and large, then, the railroader’s leisure activities were limited to solitary, individual recreations that called for no collaboration with others.
NOTER_PAGE: (349 0.5566391597899475 . 0.13241525423728814)
NOTER_PAGE: (349 0.6444111027756939 . 0.15677966101694915)
‘switching time’ sounds surprisingly similar to the Ancient Greek concept of kairos, the moment that must be seized, in the skilled work of the artisan, when ‘human action meets a natural process developing according to its own rhythm’
NOTER_PAGE: (350 0.4508627156789197 . 0.21504237288135594)
TIME AND THE OTHER IN INDUSTRIAL SOCIETY
NOTER_PAGE: (351 0.2145536384096024 . 0.13241525423728814)
Indeed to people who are accus- tomed, as many of us are, to labour timed by the clock, the attitudes to work and time of allegedly traditional or ‘primitive’ folk, who are not, are almost bound to appear ‘wasteful and lacking in urgency’
NOTER_PAGE: (351 0.5588897224306076 . 0.3135593220338983)
The rationale for the proposed change was to try to reduce the ‘porosity’ of the working day, that is, the length of time during which a man might not, in fact, be doing anything but waiting around for the next train.
NOTER_PAGE: (351 0.8147036759189797 . 0.13241525423728814)
ASLEF’s main objection was that flexible rostering would leave men with much less control than before over the scheduling of their personal and social lives.
NOTER_PAGE: (352 0.09152288072018004 . 0.5233050847457628)
At issue, then, was not the amount of time outside work, but control over the timing of this time.
NOTER_PAGE: (352 0.17104276069017255 . 0.7097457627118644)
more than a passing similarity between Sahlins’s portrayal of the intermittent, stop-go pattern of work in hunter-gatherer communities, and British Rail’s view of its drivers, as spending the greater part of the working day waiting (chatting, resting, playing cards, drinking cups of tea) between trains.
NOTER_PAGE: (352 0.5258814703675919 . 0.2044491525423729)
On weaving a basket
Of string bags and birds' nests: skill and the construction of artefacts
The dynamics of technical change
THE EVOLUTION OF TECHNOLOGY AND ITS HISTORY
NOTER_PAGE: (377 0.7929482370592649 . 0.13559322033898305)
MEASURING TECHNOLOGICAL COMPLEXITY
NOTER_PAGE: (381 0.5581395348837209 . 0.13665254237288135)
NOTER_PAGE: (381 0.5918979744936235 . 0.2838983050847458)
But comparisons based on the structural properties of the tools themselves can be misleading. Returning the objects to the contexts of their use reveals a different picture. The Inuit harpoon is a rather specialised piece of equipment, which is used only for sealing. The reindeer herdsman’s lasso, by contrast, can be put to use in all manner of different ways.
NOTER_PAGE: (382 0.49962490622655664 . 0.1281779661016949)
NOTER_PAGE: (383 0.26406601650412603 . 0.6483050847457628)
Resilience vs Efficiency
NOTER_PAGE: (384 0.13953488372093023 . 0.5116525423728814)
Techne
THE ORGANIC ANALOGY
NOTER_PAGE: (384 0.3345836459114779 . 0.11228813559322035)
'People like us': the concept of the anatomically modern human
Speech, writing and the modern origins of 'language origins'
THE LANGUAGE CAPACITY: ORIGINS OF AN ILLUSION
NOTER_PAGE: (407 0.436609152288072 . 0.13559322033898305)
NOTER_PAGE: (408 0.4838709677419355 . 0.659957627118644)
It is not, then, writing per se, but rather a technologised concep- tion of writing, associated with the rise of modern print literacy, that leads to the objectification of speech as language, and thence to the problematic of language origins.
NOTER_PAGE: (408 0.5911477869467368 . 0.3326271186440678)
THE STANDARD MODEL: GENETIC BASES OF CULTURAL TRANSMISSION
NOTER_PAGE: (408 0.6661665416354089 . 0.11016949152542373)
NOTER_PAGE: (410 0.26706676669167295 . 0.11016949152542373)
THE ARCHITECTURE OF THE MIND: ITS CONSTRUCTION AND FURNISHING
NOTER_PAGE: (411 0.37509377344336087 . 0.538135593220339)
THE MYTH OF THE LANGUAGE ACQUISITION DEVICE
NOTER_PAGE: (412 0.6331582895723932 . 0.10063559322033898)
WRITING, PRINT LITERACY AND THE MODERN CONCEPTION OF LANGUAGE
NOTER_PAGE: (414 0.4246061515378845 . 0.1059322033898305)
implications of the notion that language is fully describable
NOTER_PAGE: (414 0.48762190547636913 . 0.3644067796610169)
every verbal composition must exist initially as an entity in its own right
NOTER_PAGE: (414 0.5243810952738185 . 0.1652542372881356)
NOTER_PAGE: (414 0.5543885971492873 . 0.6673728813559322)
NOTER_PAGE: (414 0.660165041260315 . 0.3908898305084746)
one domain of activity where the conditions outlined above approxi- mately obtain – and this is the activity of writing.
NOTER_PAGE: (414 0.7186796699174794 . 0.2680084745762712)
As units of linguistic analysis, the phoneme, the word and the sentence are all artefacts of writing that, far from being intrinsic to speech, have latterly been imposed upon it
NOTER_PAGE: (415 0.12611464968152866 . 0.5998201438848921)
For what is not writable, and therefore lost in the transcription, is everything that gives the spoken utterance its ‘illocutionary force’
NOTER_PAGE: (415 0.39999999999999997 . 0.3965827338129497)
Speech Acts
Much of the history of literacy may be understood as a struggle to compensate for this limitation,
NOTER_PAGE: (415 0.45159235668789804 . 0.72931654676259)
IF SPEAKING IS A SKILL, IS WRITING A TECHNOLOGY?
NOTER_PAGE: (416 0.08917197452229299 . 0.11241007194244605)
First, skills are not techniques of the body considered, objectively and in isolation, as an instrument in the service of culture. They are rather properties of the whole system of relations constituted by the presence of the practitioner in his or her environment. Secondly, skilled practice is not just the mechanical application of external force but is continually responsive both to changing environmental conditions and to the nuances of the practitioner’s relation to the material as the task unfolds. Thirdly, skills are refractory to codification in the programmatic form of rules and representations. Thus it is not through the transmission of any such programmes that skills are learned, but rather through a mixture of improvisation and imitation in the settings of practice.
NOTER_PAGE: (416 0.2573248407643312 . 0.4352517985611511)
Techne
NOTER_PAGE: (417 0.543312101910828 . 0.24550359712230216)
Orality and Literacy
THE ART OF WRITING
NOTER_PAGE: (417 0.7503184713375796 . 0.12949640287769784)
postural change adopted by Sumerian scribes when they started writing on large rectan- gular clay tablets rather than small square ones was probably responsible for the 90° rotation of all the originally pictographic signs of the cuneiform script
NOTER_PAGE: (418 0.2127388535031847 . 0.10791366906474821)
To view writing as an art is to think of it, in the first place, as a kind of dextrous movement, and to think of the text (recalling a distinction introduced in Chapter Eighteen (pp. 346–8)) as something woven rather than made.
NOTER_PAGE: (418 0.7152866242038216 . 0.13219424460431656)
derivation of the word ‘text’ from the Latin texere, meaning ‘to weave’
NOTER_PAGE: (419 0.09044585987261146 . 0.28507194244604317)
HISTORY AS AN EVOLUTIONARY PROCESS: THE ILLUSION OF ORIGINS
NOTER_PAGE: (419 0.28662420382165604 . 0.13489208633093525)
speaking is no more or less ‘instinctive’ than writing.
NOTER_PAGE: (419 0.386624203821656 . 0.45683453237410077)
It is, I suggest, the inherent ‘logocentrism’ of modern Western thought, its understanding of practice as rule-governed execution, that renders writing as a technological system.
NOTER_PAGE: (419 0.6579617834394904 . 0.13489208633093525)
there is no such thing as technology, or language, or intelligence, at least in pre-modern or non-Western societies.
NOTER_PAGE: (421 0.7999999999999999 . 0.7086330935251799)
NOTER_PAGE: (422 0.24713375796178344 . 0.1510791366906475)
LANGUAGE, MUSIC AND SONG
NOTER_PAGE: (422 0.6312101910828025 . 0.11330935251798561)
orthodox view has it that words refer to concepts. And concepts are the building blocks of comprehensive mental representations. At once there is presupposed a division between a subject, in whose mind these representations are to be found, and an objective world ‘out there’.
NOTER_PAGE: (423 0.5254777070063694 . 0.1366906474820144)
although it is indisputable that verbal conventions are deployed in speech, such conventions do not come ready made. They are forever being built up over time, through a cumulative history of past usage: each is a hard-won product of the hazardous efforts of generations of predecessors to make themselves understood.
NOTER_PAGE: (424 0.5573248407643312 . 0.20323741007194246)
far from deriving their meanings from their attachment to mental concepts which are imposed upon a meaningless world of entities and events ‘out there’, words gather their meanings from the relational properties of the world itself. Every word is a compressed and compacted history.
NOTER_PAGE: (424 0.7133757961783439 . 0.5926258992805755)
EMOTION AND REASON
NOTER_PAGE: (425 0.289171974522293 . 0.13758992805755396)
what are rather primly called ‘curse words’ do not really merit inclusion within the domain of language at all! Language proper comes to be marked out, through the exclusion of all vocal expression of emotion, as a realm of propositional statements delivered completely free from emotional or affective overtones. Gordon Hewes suggests an example: ‘The message “the house is on fire” can, if need be, be conveyed with no more excitement than the information that Paris is a city in France’
NOTER_PAGE: (426 0.1592356687898089 . 0.3039568345323741)
The influence of writing on modern ideas and practices of language cannot be overestimated (Harris 1980: 6). For writing is not simply the equivalent of speech in an alternative medium. It is rather a kind of reconstructed, as if speech: as if the verbal utterance were fully amenable to system- atic analysis in terms of syntactical rules; as if the tone of voice and pronunciation were entirely dispensable to meaning; as if the utterance had an autonomous existence, independently of the context of its production.
NOTER_PAGE: (427 0.5681528662420382 . 0.5170863309352518)
TECHNOLOGY, ART AND CRAFTSMANSHIP
NOTER_PAGE: (428 0.21146496815286622 . 0.11241007194244605)
NOTER_PAGE: (429 0.22675159235668788 . 0.20953237410071943)
COGNITION AND PRACTICE
NOTER_PAGE: (429 0.7694267515923566 . 0.13848920863309352)
parallel to that of the linguist who assumes that the ‘languages’ of non-literate peoples exist fully-formed in the minds of speakers, merely awaiting explicit formulation. One wonders, then, what such a logos of ’cello- playing or lasso-throwing would look like. It would consist, presumably, in a set of formal rules or algorithms capable of combining elementary motor schemata into complex, patterned sequences which, precisely executed, should produce instrumental gestures appropriate to any given context.
NOTER_PAGE: (429 0.8509554140127388 . 0.5161870503597122)
NOTER_PAGE: (430 0.12356687898089172 . 0.23201438848920863)
“on pain of regress”
NOTER_PAGE: (430 0.1592356687898089 . 0.2607913669064748)
NOTER_PAGE: (430 0.6261146496815286 . 0.7401079136690648)
The map can be a help in beginning to know the country, but the aim is to learn the country, not the map.
NOTER_PAGE: (430 0.8528662420382165 . 0.7077338129496403)
‘understanding in practice’, to which she counterposes ‘the culture of acquisition’.
NOTER_PAGE: (431 0.24522292993630573 . 0.658273381294964)
Learning, in this view, entails an internalisation of collective representations or, in a word, enculturation. ‘Understanding in practice’, by contrast, is a process of enskilment,
NOTER_PAGE: (431 0.38025477707006367 . 0.6924460431654677)
INTELLIGENCE AND IMAGINATION
NOTER_PAGE: (432 0.08917197452229299 . 0.10611510791366907)
A being who is dwelling in the world, however, does not encounter stones. He encoun- ters missiles, anvils, axes or whatever, depending on the project in which he is currently engaged. They are available for him to use in much the same way as are the mouth, hands and feet.
NOTER_PAGE: (432 0.43057324840764327 . 0.12769784172661872)
what kind of activity does not involve a palpable engagement in the world? The answer is that it is activity of the special kind we call imagining.
NOTER_PAGE: (432 0.762420382165605 . 0.1960431654676259)
understand the relationship between these two generative movements, a relationship that might be characterised, provisionally, as rehearsal. One may, in imagination, ‘go over’ the same movement as a preparation or pre-run for its practical enactment. But the enactment no more issues from the image than does the latter from an image for imagining.
NOTER_PAGE: (433 0.46942675159235664 . 0.1393884892086331)
Notes
References
Index
Notes that link to this note